S. S. STEVENS 8 Measurement, Statistics And The Schemapiric View

1y ago
23 Views
2 Downloads
5.77 MB
14 Pages
Last View : 15d ago
Last Download : 3m ago
Upload by : Amalia Wilborn
Transcription

SMEASUREMENT, STATISTICS AND THE SCHEMAPIRIC VIEW12. Sicgcl, S.Nonparametric statistics fin thebehavioral sciences. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1956.13. Stevens, S. S. A scale for the measurement of apsychological magnitude: loudness. Psycho!.Rev., 1936, 43, 405-416.14. Stevens, S. S. On the problem of scales for themeasurement of psychological magnitudes.J. Unif. Sci.,1939,9,94 - 99.15. Stevens, S. S. On the theory of scales of measurement. Science, 1946, 103, 677-680.16. Stevens, S. S. Mathematics, measurement, andpsychophysics. In S. S. Stevens (ed.), Hand-101book of experimental psychology. Ncw York :Wiley, 1951, pp. 1 -49.17. Stevens, S. S. The measurement of loudness.J. Acouct. Soc. Amer., 1955, 27, 815-829.18. Stevens, S. S. On the averaging of data.Science, 1955, 121, 113-116.19. Stevens, S. S. On the psychophysicalPsychol. Rer.,1957, 64, 153 - 181.20. Stevens, S. S., and Galanter, E. H. Ratioscales and category scales for a dozen perceptual continua. J. Exp. Psycho!., 1957, 54,377-411.S. S. STEVENS8 Measurement, Statistics and theSchemapiric ViewA%curious antagonism has sometimes infectedthe relations between measurement and statistics. What ought to proceed as a pact ofmutual assistance has seemed to some authorsto justify a feud that centers on the degree ofindependence of the two domains. ThusHumphreys (1) dispenses praise to a textbookbecause its authors "do not follow the Stevensdictum concerning the precise relationshipsbetween scales of measurement and permissible statistical operations." Since that dictum,so-called, lurks as the bite noire behindmany recurrent complaints, there is need toreexamine its burden and to ask how measurement and statistics shape up in the scientificprocess—the schemapiric endeavor in whichwe invent schematic models to map empiricaldomains.In those disciplines where measurement isnoisy, uncertain, and difficult, it is only naturalthat statistics should flourish. Of course, ifthere were no measurement at all, there wouldbe no statistics. At the other extreme, ifaccurate measurement were achieved in everyinquiry, many of the needs for statistics wouldvanish. Somewhere between the two extremesof no measurement and perfect measurement,perhaps near the psychosocial-behavioralcenter of gravity, the ratio of statisticizingto measuring reaches its maximum And thatis where we find an acute sensitivity to thesuggestion that the type of measurementachieved in an experiment may set bounds onthe kinds of statistics that will prove appropriate.After reviewing the issues Anderson (2)concluded that "the statistical test can hardlybe cognizant of the empirical meaning of thenumbers with which it deals. Consequently,"he continued, "the validity of the statisticalinference cannot depend on the type ofmeasuring scale used." This sequitur, if wemay call it that, demands scrutiny, for itcompresses large issues into a few phrases.Here let me observe merely that, howevermuch we may agree that the statistical testFrom Science, Vol. 161, 30 August 1968, pp. 849-56. Copyright C , 1968 by the American Association forthe Advancement of Science. Reprinted by permission.

102MEASUREMENT AND SCA1.1.-.Scannot he cognizant of the empirical meaningof the numbers, the same privilege of ignor-of substantive content, an adventure of postu-ance can scarcely be extended to experimen-and empirical measurement were as warp andters.woof, interpenetrating each other so closelySpeaking as a statistician, Savage (3) said,"I know of no reason to limit statistical procedures to those involving arithmetic opera-that our ancestors thought it proper to provetions consistent with the scale properties ofthe observed quantities." A statistician, like acomputer, may perhaps feign indifference tothe origin of the numbers that enter into astatistical computation, but that indifferenceis not likely to be shared by the scientist. Theman in the laboratory may rather suspect that,if something empirically useful is to emergein the printout, something empirically meaningful must be programed for the input.Baker, Hardyck, and Petrinovich (4)summed up the distress: "If Stevens' positionis correct, it should be emphasized more intensively; if it is incorrect, something shouldbe done to alleviate the lingering feelings ofguilt that plague research workers who deliberately use statistics such as t on weakmeasurements." If it is true that guilt mustcome before repentence, perhaps the age ofstatistical indifference to the demands ofmeasurement may be drawing to a close.Whatever the outcome, the foregoing samplesof opinion suggest that the relation betweenstatistics and measurement is not a settledissue. Nor is it a simple issue, for it exhibitsboth theoretical and practical aspects. Moreover, peace is not likely to be restored untilboth the principles and the pragmatics havebeen resolved.SSSlate and theorem. In early ages mathematicsto countingor to some other act of measurement. Thearithmetic theorems by resortdivorce took place only in recent times. Andmathematics now enjoys full freedom to SS"play upon symbols," as Gauss phrased it,with no constraints imposed by the demandsof empirical measurement.So also with other formal orschematicsystems. The propositions of a formal logicexpress tautologies that say nothing about theworld of tangible stuff. They are analyticstatements, so-called, and they stand apartfrom the synthetic statements that expressfacts and relations among empirical objects.The Schemapiric PrincipleThere is a useful distinction to be made between the analytic, formal, syntactical propositions of logic and the synthetic, empiricalstatements of substantive discourse.Sometimes the line may be hard to draw.Quine (5) the logician denies, in fact, that anysharp demarcation can be certified, and debate on the issue between him and Carnaphas reached classic if unresolved proportions.For the scientist, meanwhile, the usefulnessof the formal-empirical distinction need notbe imperiled by the difficulty of makingrigorous decisions in borderline cases. It isuseful to distinguish between day and nightdespite the penumbral passage through twilight. So also is it useful to tune ourselves todistinguish between the formally schematicand the empirical substantive.Probability exhibits the same double aspect,the same schemapiric nature. MathematicalAlthough measurement began in the empirical mode, with the accent on the countingof moons and paces and warriors, it was destined in modern times to find itself debatedin the formal, schematic, syntactical mode,where models can be made to bristle withsymbols. Mathematics, which like 1p,gicconstitutes a formal endeavor, was not alwaysregarded as an arbitrary construction devoidtheories of probability inhabit the formalrealm as analytic, tautologous, schematicsystems, and they say nothing at all aboutdice, roulette, or lotteries. On the empiricallevel, however, we count and tabulate eventsat the gaming table or in the laboratory andnote their relative frequencies. Sometimes therelative frequencies stand in isomorphicrelation to some property of a mathematicalSSSSSSSS SS SSSSSSSS

MLASUREMENT, STATISTICS AND THU. SCH[MAPIRIC VIl wmodel of probability; at other times the observed frequencies exhibit scant accord with"expectations."Those features of statistics that involve aprobabilistic schema provide a further instanceof a formal-empirical dichotomy: the distinction between the probability model andthe statistical data. E. B. Wilson (6), mathematician and statistician, made the point "thatone must distinguish critically betweenprobability as a purely mathematical subjectof one sort or another, and statistics whichcannot be so regarded." Statistics, of course,is a young discipline—one whose voicechanges depending on who speaks for it.Many spokesmen would want to broadenthe meaning of statistics to include a formal,mathematical segment.In another context N. R. Hanson (7)pressed a similar distinction when he said,"Mathematics and physics on this accountseem logically different disciplines, such thatthe former can only occasionally solve thelatter's problems." Indeed, as Hanson laterexclaimed, "Physicists have in unison pronounced, 'Let no man join what nature hathsundered, namely, the formal creation ofspaces and the physical description of bodies.' "Yet it is precisely by way of the proper andjudicious joining of the schematic withthe empirical that we achieve our beneficialand effective mappings of the universe—theschemapiric mappings known as science.The chronic danger lies in our failure to notethe distinction between the map and theterrain, between the simulation and the simulated. The map is an analogue, a schema, amodel, a theory. Each of those words has aseparate flavor, but they all share a commoncore of meaning. "Contrary to general belief,"wrote Simon and Newell (8), "there is nofundamental, 'in principle,' difference betweentheories and analogies. All theories are analogies, and all analogies are theories." Indeed,the same can be said for all the other termsthat designate the associative binding ofschematics to empirics—what I have calred theschemapiric bond.103Scales and lnvarianccAlthough it could be otherwise if our choicedictated, most measurement involves theassignment of numbers to aspects of objectsor events according to one or another ruleor convention. The variety of rules inventedthus far for the assignment of numbers hasalready grown enormous, and novel means ofmeasuring continue to emerge. It has provedpossible, however, to formulate an invariancecriterion for the classification of scales ofmeasurement (9). The resulting systemizationof scale Types has found uses in contextsranging from physics (10) to the social sciences(11), but the conception has not enjoyedimmunity from criticism (12).Let me sketch the theory. It can be donevery briefly, because details are given in otherplaces (13). The theory proposes that a scaletype is defined by the group of transformationsunder which the scale form remains invariant,as follows.A nominal scale admits any one-to-onesubstitution of the assigned numbers. Example of a nominal scale: the numbering of football players.An ordinal scale can be transformed byany increasing monotonic function. Exampleof an ordinal scale: the hardness scale determined by the ability of one mineral to scratchanother.An interval scale can be subjected to alinear transformation. Examples of intervalscales: temperature Fahrenheit and Celsius,calendar time, potential energy.A ratio scale admits only multiplicationby a constant. Examples of ratio scales:length, weight, density, temperature Kelvin,time intervals, loudness in sones.The foregoing scales represent the fourtypes in common use. Other types are possible.The permissible transformations defining ascale type are those that keep intact the empirical information depicted by the scale.If the empirical information has been preserved, the scale form is said to remain invariant. The critical isomorphism is main-

MEASUREMENT AND SCALES104Table I. Examples of statistical measures appropt iate to measurements made on varioustypes of scales. The scale type is defined by the manner in which scale numbers can betransformed without the loss of empirical information. The statistical measures listedarc those that remain invariant, as regards either value or reference, under the transformations allowed by the scale type.ScaletipeMeasures oflocationAssociation k entilesIntervalArithmetic elation ratioAveragedeviationPercent variationDecilogdispersionSignificancetestsChi squareFisher'sexact testSign testRun testRatioGeometric meanHarmonic meantained. That indeed is the principle of invariance that lies at the heart of the conception.More formal presentations of the foregoingtheory have been undertaken by other authors,a recent one, for example, by Lea (14).Unfortunately, those who demand anabstract tidiness that is completely asepticmay demur at the thought that the decisionwhether a particular scale enjoys the privilegeof a particular transformation group dependson something so ill defined as the preservationof empirical information. For one thing,an empirical operation is always attended byerror. Thus Lebesgue (15), who strove so wellto perfect the concept of mathematicalmeasure, took explicit note that, in the assignment of number to a physical magnitude,precision can be pushed, as he said, "inactuality only up to a certain error. It neverenables us," he continued, "to discriminatebetween one number and all the numbers thatare extremely close to it."A second disconcerting feature of the invariance criterion lies in the difficulty ofspecifying the empirical information that is tobe preserved. What can it be other than theinformation that we think we have capturedby creating the scale in the first place? W.emay, for example, perform operations thatr testF testallow us simply to identify or discriminate aparticular property of an object. Sometimeswe want to preserve nothing more than thatsimple outcome, the identification or nominalclassification of the items of interest. Or wemay go further, provided our empiricaloperations permit, and determine rank orders,equal intervals, or equal ratios. If we want ournumber assignments to reflect one or anotheraccrual in information, we are free to transform the scale numbers only in a way thatdoes not lose or distort the desired information. The choice remains ours.Although some writers have found it possible to read an element of prescription—evenproscription—into the invariance principle,as a systematizing device the principle contains no normative force. It can be read moreas a description of the obvious than as adirective. It says that, once an isomorphismhas been mapped out between aspects ofobjects or events, on the one hand, and someone or more features of the number system,on the other hand, the isomorphism can beupset by whatever transformations fail topreserve it. Precisely what is preserved or notpreserved in a particular circumstance depends upon the empirical operations. Sinceactual day-to-day measurements range from

MLASURLMEN1, STATIST ICS ANDSCHENIAPIRIC105Simuddled to meticulous, our ability to classifythem in terms of scale type must range fromhopelessly uncertain to relatively secure.111type serves in turn to delimit the statisticalstatistical computations may proceed as freelyas in any other syntactical exercise, unimpededprocedures that can be said to be appropriateby any material outcome of empirical meas-to a given measurement scale (16). Examplesurement. Nor does measurement have a presumptive voice in the creation of the statisticalmodels themselves. As Hogben (18) said inhis forthright dissection of statistical theory,"It is entirely defensible to formulate anaxiomatic approach to the theory of probability as an internally consistent set of propositions, if one is content to leave to thosein closer contact with reality the last wordThe group invariance that defines a scaleare tabulated inTable 1. Under the permissible transformations of a measurement scale, some appropriate statistics remain invariant in value(example: the correlation coefficient r keepsits value under linear transformations).Other statistics change value but refer to thesame item or location (example: the medianchanges its value but continues to referto mid-distribution under ordinal transformaof appropriate statisticsII.11 )1111tions).p11into the mathematical system, nonsense issure to come out."At the level of the formal model, then,Reconciliation and New ProblemsTwo developments may serve to ease theapprehension among those who may havefelt threatened by a theory of measurementthat seems to place bounds on our freedom11to calculate. One is a clearer understanding111of the bipartite, schemapiric nature of thescientific enterprise. When the issue concerns2only the schema—when, for example, criticalratios are calculated for an assumed binomial11 distribution—then indeed it is purely a matterof relations within a mathematical model.Natural facts stand silent. Empirical considerations impose no constraints. When,however, the text asserts a relation among suchthings as measured differences or variabilities,we have a right and an obligation to inquireabout the operations that underlie the measurements. Those operations determine, in turn,the type of scale achieved.The two-part schemapiric view was ex% pressed by Hays (17) in a much-praised book :"If the statistical method involves the procedures of arithmetic used on numericalscores, then the numerical answer is formally11 correct.The difficulty comes with the interpretation of these numbers back into statements about the real world. If nonsense is put11on the usefulness of the outcome." Both Haysand Hogben insist that the user of statistics,the man in the laboratory, the maker ofmeasurements, must decide the meaning ofthe numbers and their capacity to advanceempirical inquiry.The second road to reconciliation windsthrough a region only partly explored, aregion wherein lies the pragmatic problem ofappraising the wages of transgression. Whatis the degree of risk entailed when use is madeof statistics that may be inappropriate inthe strict sense that they fail the test ofinvariance under permissible scale transformations? Specifically, let us assume that a set ofitems can be set in rank order, but, by theoperations thus far invented, distances between the items cannot be determined. Wehave an ordinal but not an interval scale.What happens then if interval-scale statisticsare applied to the ordinally scaled items?Therein lies a question of first-rate substanceand one that should be amenable to unemotional investigation. It promises well that afew answers have already been forthcoming.First there is the oft-heeded counsel ofcommon sense. In the averaging of test scores,says Mosteller (19), "It seems sensible to usethe statistics appropriate to the type of scaleI think I am near. In taking such action we mayfind the justification vague and fuzzy. Onereason for this vagueness is that we have notyet studied enough about classes of scales,

MLASUR II NI ENT A ND SCA L 11Sclasses appropriate to real life measurement,with perhaps real life bias and crror variance."How sonic of the vagueness of whichMosteller spoke can perhaps be removed isillustrated by the study of Abelson and Tukcy(20) who showed how bounds may be determined for the risk involved when an intervalscale statistic is used with an ordinal scale.Specifically, they explored the effect on r2 of agame against nature in which nature does itsbest (or worsi!) to minimize the value of r 2 .In this game of regression analysis, manyinteresting cases were explored, but, as theauthors said, their methods need extension toother cases. They noted that we often knowmore about ordinal data than mere rankorder. We may have reason to believe, theysaid, "that the scale is no worse than mildlycurvilinear, that Nature behaves smoothlyin some sense." Indeed the continued use ofparametric statistics with ordinal data restson that belief, a belief sustained in large measure by the pragmatic usefulness of the resultsachieved.In a more synthetic study than the foregoing analysis, Baker et al. (4) imposed sets ofmonotonic transformations on an assumedset of data, and calculated the effect on the 1distribution. The purpose was to comparedistributions of / for data drawn from anequal-interval scale with distributions of tfor several types of assumed distortions of theequal intervals. By and large, the effects on thecomputed 1 distributions were not large, andthe authors concluded "that strong statisticssuch as the t test are more than adequate tocope with weak [ordinal] measurements.".It should be noted, however, that the values oft were affected by the nonlinear transformations. As the authors said, "The correspondence between values of t based on the criterionunit interval scores and values of / based on[nonlinear] transformations decreases regularly and dramatically.as the departurefrom linear transformations becomes moreextreme."Whatever the substantive outcome of suchinvestigations may prove to be, they pointthe way to reconciliation through orderlyinquiry. Debate gives way to calculation.The question is theretoy made to turn, not onwhether the measurement scale determines thechoice of a statistical procedure, but on howand to what degree an inappropriate statisticmay lead to a deviant conclusion. The solutionof such problems may help to refurbish thecomplexion of measurement theory, whichhas been accused of proscribing those statistics that do not remain invariant under thetransformations appropriate to a given scale.By spelling out the costs, we may convert theissue from a- seeming proscription to a calculated risk.The type of measurement achieved is not,of course, the only consideration affecting theapplicability of parametric statistics. Bradleyis one of many scholars who have sifted theconsequences of violating the assumptionsthat underlie some of the common parametrictests (21). As one outcome of his studies,Bradley concluded, "The contention that,when its assumptions are violated, a parametric test is still to be preferred to a distribution-free test because it is 'more efficient'is therefore a monumental non sequitur. Thepoint is not at all academic .violations in atest's assumptions may be attended by profound changes in its power." That conclusionis not without relevance to scales of measurement, for when ordinal data are forced intothe equal-interval mold, parametric assumptions are apt to be violated. It is then that aso-called distribution-free statistic may provemore efficient than its parametric counterpart.Although better accommodation amongcertain of the contending statistical usagesmay be brought about by computer-aidedstudies, there remain many statistics thatfind their use only with specific kinds ofscales. A single example may suffice. In aclassic text-book, written with a captivating clarity, Peters and Van Voorhis (22) gothung up on a minor point concerning theprocedure to be used in comparing variabilities. They noted that Karl Pearson hadproposed a measure called the coefficient of

MIIASUREMENT, STATISTICS AND 1HL SCHI.NIAPIR1C Hvariation, which expresses the standard deviation as a percentage of the mean. The authors107alluded to that need in his discourse on thenature of probability (24). "I am quite sure, –hesaid,"tonlyprcawitheexpressed doubts about its value, however,because it tells "more about the extent tobusiness of the improvement of natural know-which the scores are padded by a dislocationof the zero point than it does about comparable variabilities." The examples and arguments given by the authors make it plainthat the coefficient of variation has little business being used with what I have called interval scales. But since their book antedated mypublication in 1946 of the defining invariancesfor interval and ratio scales, Peters and VanVoorhis did not have a convenient way to statethe relationship made explicit in Table 1,namely, that the coefficient of variation, beingitself a ratio, called for a ratio scale.ledge in the natural sciences that is capableComplexities and PitfallsConcepts like relative variability have thevirtue of being uncomplicated and easy for thescientist to grasp. They fit his idiom. But inthe current statistics explosion, which showersthe investigator with a dense fallout of newstatistical models, the scientist is likely to losethe thread on many issues. It is then that thetheory of measurement, with an anchorhooked fast in empirical reality, may serve as asanctuary against the turbulence of specializedabstraction."As a mathematical discipline travels farfrom its empirical source," said von Neumann(23), "there is grave danger that the subjectwill develop along the line of least resistance,that the stream, so far from its source, willseparate into a multitude of insignificantbranches, and that the discipline will becomea disorganized mass of details and complexities." He went on to say that, "After much abstract' inbreeding, a mathematical subjectis in danger of degeneration. At the inceptionthe style is usually classical; when it showssigns of becoming baroque, then the dangersignal is up."There is a sense, one suspects, in whichstatistics needs measurement moi. e thanmeasurement needs statistics. R. A. Fisherthought of mathematically-minded people who have to grope theirway through the complex entanglements oferror."And lest the physical sciences should seemimmune to what Schwartz (25) called "thepernicious influence of mathematics," considerhis diagnosis: "Thus, in its relations withscience, mathematics depends on an intellectual effort outside of mathematics for thecrucial specification of the approximationwhich mathematics is to take literally. Give amathematician a situation which is the leastbit ill-defined—he will first of all make it welldefined. Perhaps appropriately, but perhapsalso inappropriately.That form of wisdomwhich is the opposite of single-mindedness,the ability to keep many threads in hand,to draw for an argument from many disparatesources, is quite foreign to mathematics.Quite typically, science leaps ahead and mathematics plods behind."Progress in statistics often follows asimilar road from practice to prescription—from field trials to the formalization of principles. As Kruskal (26) said "Theoretical studyof a statistical procedure often comes after itsintuitive proposal and use." Unfortunatelyfor the empirical concerns of the practitioners,however, there is, as Kruskal added, "almostno end to the possible theoretical study ofeven the simplest procedure." So the disciplinewanders far from its empirical source, andform loses sight of substance.Not only do the forward thrusts of scienceoften precede the mopping-up campaignsof the mathematical schema builders, butmeasurement itself may often find implementto keep straight theation only after some basic conception hasbeen voiced. Textbooks, those distilled artificesof science, like to picture scientific conceptionsas built on measurement, but the workingscientist is more apt to devise his measure-

log MLASUREMLN1 AND SCALESments to suit his conceptions. As Kuhn (27)said, "The route from theory or law to measurement can almost never be travelled backwards. Numbers gathered without sonicknowledge of the regularity to be expectedalmost never to speak for themselves. Almostcertainly they remain just numbers." Yet whowould deny that some ears, more tuned tonumbers, may hear them speak in freshand revealing ways?The intent here is not, of course, to affrontthe qualities of a discipline as useful asmathematics. Its virtues and power are toogreat to need extolling, but in power lies acertain danger. For mathematics, like a computer, obeys commands and asks no questions.It will process any input, however devoid ofscientific sense, and it will bedeck in formulasboth the meaningful and the absurd. In thebehavioral sciences, where the discernmentfor nonsense is perhaps less sharply honedthan in the physical sciences, the vigil mustremain especially alert against the intrusionof a defective theory merely because it carriesa mathematical visa. An absurdity in fullformularized attire may be more seductivethan an absurdity undressed.Distributions and DecisionsThe scientist often scales items, counts them,and plots their frequency distributions. He issometimes interested in the form of suchdistributions. If his data have been obtainedfrom measurements made on interval or ratioscales, the shape of the distribution stays put(up to a scale factor) under those transformations that are permissible, namely, those thatpreserve the empirical information containedin the measurements. The principle seemsstraightforward. But what happens when thestate of the art can produce no more than arank ordering, and hence nothing better thanan ordinal scale? The abscissa of the frequency distribution then loses its metricmeaning and becomes like a rubber band,capable of all sorts of monotonic stretch-ings.With each non-linear transformation of the scale, the form of the distribution ch:inues.Thereupon the distribution loses structure,SSSSand we find it futile to ask whether the shapeapproximates a particular form, whethernormal, rectangular, or whatever.Working on the formal level, the statisticianmay contrive a schematic model by firstassuming a frequency function, or a distribution function, of one kind or another. At theabstract level of mathematical creation, therecan, of course, be no quarrel with the statistician's approach to his task. The cautionlight turns on, however, as soon as the modelis asked to mirror an empirical domain.We must then invoke a set of semantic rules—coordinating definitions—in order to identifycorrespondences between model and reality.What shall we say about the frequencyfunction f(x) when the problem before us allows only an ordinal scale? Shall x be subjectto a nonlinear transformation after f(x)has been specified? If so, what does the transformation do to the model and to the predictions it forecasts?The scientist has reason to feel that a statistical model that specifies the form of a canonical distribution becomes uninterpretable whenthe empirical domain concerns only ordinaldata. Yet many consumers of statistics seemto disregard what to others is a rather obviousand critical problem. Thus Burke (28) proposed to draw "two random samples frompopulations known to be normal" and then"to test the hypothesis that the two populations have the same mean. under the assump-S S SSSSSSSS Stion that the scale is ordinal at best." How,we must ask, can normality be known whenonly order can be certified ?The assu

14. Stevens, S. S. On the problem of scales for the measurement of psychological magnitudes. J. Unif. Sci.,1939,9,94-99. 15. Stevens, S. S. On the theory of scales of meas-urement. . because its authors "do not follow the Stevens dictum concerning the precise relationships between scales of measurement and permissi-ble statistical operations .

Related Documents:

Computer Engineering, Stevens Institute of Technology, Hoboken, NJ 07030 hong.man@stevens. edu). A. Ritter is with the Department of Chemistry, Chemical Biology, and Biomedical Engineering, Stevens Institute of Technology, Hoboken, NJ 07030

Grade (9-1) _ 58 (Total for question 1 is 4 marks) 2. Write ̇8̇ as a fraction in its simplest form. . 90. 15 blank Find the fraction, in its

4 School of Business and Economics University of Wisconsin-Stevens Point 5 The UW-Stevens Point School of Business and Economics (SBE) has made great leaps in recent years. It still offers the same educational foundation many of its proud alumni reflect back on, but the school has grown and evolved. Since 2008, increased demand and new

1974. The normal school which opened in Stevens Point in 1894 became a part of the University of Wisconsin System with the actions of the legislature in the early 1970s. It is the intent of this book to trace the history of the campus at Stevens Point, created as a normal school in 1893, opening in 1894, and

1800 North Point Drive, Stevens Point, WI 54481 1-800-739-3344. WC-80-10-0010 (Ed.7/06) 10-06 Sentry Insurance Group . Sentry Insurance Group Name 1800 North Point Drive, Stevens Point, Wisconsin 54481 1-800-739-3344 Address Phone IF YOU HAVE QUESTIONS, PLEASE CONTACT THE STATE BOARD OF WORKERS' COMPENSATION AT 404-656-3818 OR 1-800-533-0682 .

28-39), to preclude summary judgment Utah law required Stevens-Henager only to provide evidence that Eagle Gate's illegal conduct proximately caused damages, not to quantify those damages. As demonstrated below, Stevens-Henager provided evidence that Eagle Gate's conduct was the proximate cause of numerous categories of damages. 3

Stevens Institute of Technology Castle Point on Hudson Hoboken, N.J. 07030 Phone 201.216.5263 Fax 201.216.8909 www.soe.stevens.edu S S O E S S O E 10 Engineering Our Future N.J. SPRING 2006 ISSUE VOLUME 4 11 The Green Bullet U.S.-Greek Alliance: Protecting and Restoring the Environment The mission of the conference is to: Exchange .

Army Regulation 135-91 (Service Obligations, Methods of Fulfillment, . Travel alone poses a safety issue as mothers of newborns this age usually have interrupted sleep due to night-time feedings and diaper changes. This makes driving longer distances unsafe. There are also safety issues for the newborn related to SIDS as described below under the American Academy of Pediatrics research .