? Nietzsche And The Machine - WordPress

1y ago
18 Views
3 Downloads
1.44 MB
22 Pages
Last View : 10d ago
Last Download : 3m ago
Upload by : Abby Duckworth
Transcription

T H I N K I N G AT I T S L I M I T S214(a decision does ot wait, theGerard Huber has distinguished between . . .ed) . Well then, SInce we. decision cannot wait for levels to be distinguishfor these level be distm not wait for these oppositions to be analyzed,.ctory con lt on to beguished, for the discussion to be over and for satisfacy and precIpItatIOn arefound to act and make decisions, given that urgenhere i to discove and topart of the very essence of the decision, ur d.utyto say, wIthout ainvent, each and every time, in singular sItuatIOns, that ISex ?le. Thus,etAndgiven rule. Our duty is to invent, to give the rule . .It IS vertIgInOUs, butnot to wait and to know how to wait at the same tIme.ait, while hol ing on only in this situation can decisions be made. ot to ; a responsIble decI self back nonetheless to continue to reconsIder thmgsvigilance, as doession if there is one, always comes at this price, as doesif this is possible.er,slumbeve hing that might tear us from our dogmatic Nietzsche and the Machine R B . : It has been an insistent point on your part, informing the read ing strategy of each of your engagements with Nietzsche's philosophy, thatthere is no one truth to Nietzsche or to Nietzsche's text. Your relations toNietzsche distinguish themselves explicitly from those of Heidegger, whichare marked by a persistent, if not anguished, desire to contain Nietzschewithin the history of Being. As you observe in Otiobiographies, "The futureof the Nietzsche text is not closed. " l I hope that my questions keep to thespirit of this remark, not only by remaining as open as possible but also be cause they concern the future(s) of Nietzsche (what Nietzsche had to say ofthe future as well as the future of Nietzsche's thought today) . I want, nev ertheless, to engage you with the Nietzsche text in relation to a specific his torical context: that of a world emerging-politically, economically, andculturally-from the Cold War. The general orientation of my questions isthus not related too intently to questions of interpretation (whether ofNietzsche's text, your texts, or your texts on Nietzsche) ; it is guided, rather,by the consideration of the name Nietzsche as an "index" of a series of prob lems that are ever-more pressing at the end of the Cold War-namely, therelations between government, technology, j ustice, and the future. Let thename of Nietzsche in this context be a way of opening up possibilities of ap proach to these problems. I should like to entitle the interview "Nietzscheand the Machine."QUESTION ONE: I will start with a very general question. When oneconsiders all the writings that you have published to date, one is struck

216T H I N K I N G AT I T S L I M I T Sby a paradox. Since "Force and Signification" in Writing and Difference,various voices of Nietzsche have intimately inhabited your work, and yet,compared to the long analyses of Husserl, Plato, Hegel, Freud, Blanchot,etc. , you have written, or at least published, few pieces explicitly onNietzsche. Is there a particular reason for this?J . D . : In response to question one-this apparent lack of sustainedreflection on Nietzsche can perhaps be explained by following one of thethreads of your introduction. I have indeed found it difficult to bring to gether or stabilize, within a particular configuration, a "thought" ofNietzsche. By the term configuration I mean not only a systematic co herence or consistency (no one has seriously tried to identify a philo sophical or speculative "system" in what is called-a proper name moreproblematic and enigmatic than ever-Nietzsche) but also the organiza tion of an ensemble, of a work or corpus, around a guiding meaning, afundamental project or even a formal feature (of writing or speech) . Itis this irreducible and singular multiplicity, this resistance to any formof Versammlung, including that of the end of metaphysics (in the sensethat Heidegger's interpretation constitutes an attempt to "arrest" comprehendere rather than verstehen-the essential elements ofNietzsche's unique thought within such an end) : it is this irreducibilitythat it has always seemed to me more j ust to respect. The diversity ofgestures of thought and writing, the contradictory mobility (withoutpossible synthesis or sublation) of the analytical incursions, the diag noses, excesses, intuitions, the theater and music of the poetic-philo sophical forms, the more-than-tragic play with masks and propernames-these "aspects" of Nietzsche's work have always appeared to meto defy, from the very beginning to the point of making them looksomewhat derisory, all the "surveys" and accounts of Nietzsche (philo sophical, metaphilosophical, psychoanalytic, or political) . As you say,several voices can be heard; they return with an insistence that, I be lieve, will never cease, and that demands these voices never be reducedto a "monology. " In this sense, such voices already resound in their fu ture, in the reserve with which, to use a very Nietzschean figure, theyare "pregnant. " What will Nietzsche's future be? This question has al ways left me on the verge of a "general repetition" of Nietzsche.That said, I have, mutatis mutandis, a similar feeling for thosethinkers to whom I have apparently devoted more lengthy analyses. WhatNietzsche and the Machine21 7I have j ust said about Nietzsche, I would also say about Plato, Hegel,Husser!, Freud, Blanchot, and so on. My writing on them remains frag mentary, oblique, elliptical, open-I hope-to surprise and to the returnof other voices. And so your question cannot be answered. Now, what isthe privilege of Nietzsche in this respect? I don't know: he is perhaps, ofthem all, the most mad! Two consequences are to be drawn from this:first, through this madness thought is perhaps unleashed all the more vi olently and with all the more freedom; second, it is unleashed with all themore suffering. As a result, one must forbid oneself-with Nietzscheabove all-to force his name into the straight jacket of an interpretationthat is too strong to be able to account for him, in that it is claiming torecognize the identity of a meaning, of a message, of the unity of a word,or of a particular work.QUESTION TWO: Your work has often been criticized for being too"Nietzschean." Informing such criticisms is a very determined reading ofNietzsche and of yourself that argues (whatever the differences of each cri tique) that your work, by following Nietzsche too closely, falls into an un critical and irresponsible irrationalism and replaces rational norms ofphilosophical thinking with the creative playfulness of art. I would like toask you two related questions in this context. First, has the predominantly"literary" reception of your work in the anglophonic world (and particu larly the United States) detracted from a certain philosophical necessity toyour consideration of the literary text? In this context it would appear thatthis necessity has been partially covered over by the accusation, leveledagainst deconstruction, of "Nietzscheanism." Second, and more particu larly, following this reception of deconstruction ("Derrida's work is ulti mately irrational and relativist") , how do you consider your relation toNietzsche in "White Mythology"? In this often misunderstood essay (asyou yourself point out to Paul Ricceur in "Le retrait de la metaphore") ,you deconstruct any attempt-and here the early Nietzsche's reduction o ftruth to metaphor i s paradigmatic of this empiricist, if not modern,attempt-to reduce the founding concepts of philosophy to the sensibleword. I will come back to the moves of this essay in a moment. Can I askyou here, how the deconstruction of Western philosophy, of which"White Mythology" is one sustained example, differs from Nietzsche'soverriding belief that the Western tradition needs to be destroyed? What arethe differences between deconstruction and destruction?

218T H I N K I N G AT I T S L I M I T SJ .D .: First, the accusation of "Nietzscheanism" makes no sense in itsown terms. As the last answer made clear, the more faithful one mayclaim to be to Nietzsche, the less one can make a claim on the identity ofa particular "feature" of Nietzsche's thought. The closer one is to"Nietzsche," the more one is aware that there is no such thing as theNietzsche-text. This text demands interpretation in the same way that itargues that there is no such thing as an entity, only interpretations active and reactive-of that entity. "To be Nietzschean" is a journalisticslogan that cannot cope with the names and pseudonyms of Nietzsche;its raison d'etre is, ultimately, to conjure away anxiety.Second, it is wrong to argue that Nietzsche is irrational and wrong,therefore, to say that deconstruction is also irrational following its passagethrough Nietzsche. This is hopelessly simplistic. There are many morenames in this historical configuration of which deconstruction forms apart than that of Nietzsche. Nietzsche, yes, but also Heidegger andBenjamin, and so forth. The term irrational fails totally to come to termswith the "method" of genealogy. The point will come up again when wediscuss question four. Genealogy is an attempt, in Nietzsche's eyes, togive an account of the history of reason. There may be problems with thisaccount, it may at times go too quickly, but as such, genealogy inscribesitself in the back of reason; it cannot be, accordingly, an irrational proce dure of thinking. The method and purpose of genealogy preceded and ex ceed such distinctions, re-organizing the tradition's identifications ofwhat is rational and what is irrational. To accuse either Nietzsche, orthose thinkers partly inspired by this account of reason, of irrationalism,is to fall back into a discursive position that genealogy exceeds.The third point concerns the question of the literary reception ofdeconstruction in the Anglo-American world. Just one remark, here,since the issue is extremely complex. If it has been the case that decon struction passed initially through literature rather than philosophy de partments, there is a clear reason for this. Literary theory, especially inAmerica, was more ready to listen to arguments and strategies of attemptsto get behind reason's back than institutional inscriptions of philosophy.The politics of these departments (or at least some of them; those whichwere receptive, precisely, to deconstruction) were, in this sense, morephilosophical.Fourth, you ask in your question what the differences are betweendeconstruction and destruction. You have said the essential in questionsNietzsche and the Machine219two and three, so let me add something else: the question of originaryaffirmation. To take up again the three thinkers Nietzsche, Heidegger,and Benjamin, it is quite clear that something is happening at the endof the nineteenth century and the beginning of the twentieth for think ing to want to affirm the future. However negative, however destructiveone's account of the history of the West may have become at this time,something is calling thought from the future; it is this call that makesboth the passage via destruction, and an affirmation within this de struction, absolutely necessary. What do I mean by this? Before settingup trib unals or criticizing particular discourses, schools, movements, oracademic tendencies, one must first admit that something is perhapshappening to humanity in the crossover from the nineteenth to thetwentieth century for affirmation, for an affirmation of the future or ofan opening onto the future, to be marked within a discourse of appar ent destruction or mourning. Think of the problem of messianicity inBenjamin, the q uestion of the future in Nietzsche, the privilege of thefutural ecstasis in Heidegger. These thinkers are all thinkers of the fu ture . . . . Now, why is it that any opening onto the future, both yester day and today, passes through what looks like a destruction, a negativedestructuration? Nor is it simply these three thinkers, either. Howeverimportant their thought may be, they are symptoms of, spokesmen forsomething that is taking place in the world-at least in the West-thatcauses affirmation to be carried through by a devastating upheaval, asort of revolution that cannot proceed without destruction, withoutseparation or interruption, or without fidelity. For these thinkers arealso thinkers of fidelity, of repetition-eternal return in Nietzsche, thequestion of Being in Heidegger, which, conveyed through an initial de struction, is presented by Heidegger as repetition, and so forth. Thesethinkers of the future are at the same time thinkers of eternal return, ofrepetition. So, my question is the following: why is it that this reaffir mation can have a future only through the seism of a destruction? Butthis is hardly a question; rather, it is the experience of what is takingplace, of the revolution that bears us along. One can describe this move ment as a seism, an earthquake, a maelstrom, or even a chaos, and thereis a certain truth to this description. For the above are thinkers of theabyss (Abgrund), of chaos, of khaein-that is, where there is an open ing, where the mouth gapes, and one does not know what to say, herethere is an experience of chaos .

220T H I N K I N G AT I T S L I M I T SIt could be argued ( I think here of GeoffreyBennington's recent appraisal of the essay in "Derridabase") that "WhiteMythology" enacts an adventure of thinking typical of deconstruction'sstrategies toward, on the one hand, the discipline of philosophy, and, onthe other hand, those of the human sciences. Your relation to the posi tion of metaphor in the philosophical text is, consequently, one forcefulenactment of deconstruction's displacement and re-organization of themetaphysical opposition between the transcendental and the empirical.To recall the major gesture of "White Mythology" : on the one hand, youshow that it is impossible to dominate philosophical metaphorics fromoutside philosophy, since the attempt meets with an essential limit in thefact that the very concept of metaphor is a philosopheme based on themetaphysical difference between the visible and the invisible, etc. Onthe other hand, and for the same reason, you argue that philosophy isincapable of dominating its metaphorical productions, since in its veryattempt it would deprive itself of that which sustains it. "WhiteMythology" traces this double impossibility leaving itself and the readerin an aporetic and uncontrollable "position, " neither inside philosophynor outside it, in another science that would wish to dominate philoso phy (linguistics, psychoanalysis, history-the list would include, pre cisely, all modern endeavors to make thought finite) .This said, I have two questions. In what way is this ambivalent "sav ing" of philosophy, its re-inscription, different from Heidegger's wish inhis Nietzsche lectures of the 19 30S to save Nietzsche's thought from hisNazi contemporaries' consideration of it as "a philosophy of life"?Heidegger opposes the anti-conceptualism of these readings by placingNietzsche within metaphysics. You have yourself suggested on various oc casions (Of Grammatology, "The End of the Book and the Beginning ofWriting," SpurslEperons: Les styles de Nietzsche, " Interpreting Signatures,Nietzsche/Heidegger: Two Questions") that Heidegger thereby"loses" Nietzsche. In what ways does your double move toward the placeof metaphor in the philosophical text save and lose Nietzsche differently?QUESTION THREE:J . D . : There are two questions in your question three. I will respondto both of them through the problematic of life. First, yes, I do not havethe same approach to Nietzsche as Heidegger does for reasons of history,of generations, and of context. I am not writing between the two worldwars. My major concern is not to prize Nietzsche from Nazi reappropri-Nietzsche and the Machine221ation. My approach is different as well, because I am deeply suspicious ofthis kind of maneuver. As I make clear in Otobiographies, it is not bychance that Nietzsche could be reappropriated by Nazism. Heidegger'shistory of Being, his metaphysics, cannot cope with this contamination.My first concern, then, is not to "save" Nietzsche, although I understandwhy Heidegger wanted to save Nietzsche by showing that his thoughtwas not simply a philosophy of life. At the same time, I am aware thatthe question of life is much more obscure and difficult than Heideggerclaims. Indeed, if there is one theme in Heidegger's work that makes mevery uneasy, it is the theme of life. I, like everyone, want to be a vigilantreader of the political risks of biologism following its particular use of theconcept of life, and yet the question of life is much trickier thanHeidegger makes out. Heidegger's gesture is, in fact, extremely equivocal:he cannot save Nietzsche from the biologism and racism in which theNazis want to enclose him except by making him a metaphysician; thelast of the metaphysicians; that is, by reducing him in turn. I have triedto formalize this scene in several texts: Heidegger saves Nietzsche by los ing him and loses him by saving him. I try to read Nietzsche-thethinker of the "perhaps" ( Vielleicht), as he says in Beyond Good and Evil in a much more suspensive manner to avoid these reductive gestures andaffirm something else.Regarding your second question, I cannot bring together anythingwhatsoever in Nietzsche, whether it concern life or anything else. On thecontrary, I am neither able to, nor want to, save Nietzsche. My relationin general to thinkers j ust does not follow this kind of logic.Deconstruction cannot pose the problem of the proper name in terms oflevels of allegiance or nonallegiance. There is no trial in this sense. Thereare, for example, discursive elements in Nietzsche that lend themselvesto Nazi reappropriation; one can discern a lineage from Nietzsche toNazism, and this cannot be ignored. At the same time, there are manyother elements, sometimes the very same elements, many other strands ofthought, sometimes the same strands, which are far from reducible to ei ther the enterprise of Nazism or that of Heidegger. As I have said in OfSpirit, Heidegger's gesture actually capitalizes on the worst-the sanc tioning of Nazism and the metaphysical counterappropriation. It is im portant in this context to take Heidegger's Nietzsche and show that thereare other possibilities in Nietzsche that are not programmed by a historyof metaphysics, that there are moves that are stronger, that go further

-"1Nietzsche and the MachineT H I N K I N G AT I T S L I M I T S222f metap ysics;than what Heidegger calls the history of the completion oreadmg ofhIsf:himselgermoves that actually put in questio n Heideggeneral.inNietzsche in particular and his philoso phical orientationto readBriefly, there exists a reserve in Nietzsche that allows oneHeidegger's own thought genealogically.Perhaps it is a little clearer now what I meant earlIer when I spokeAs forof my preference for texts that are open, multip le, fragme nted.ts that paarethereNietzsche, there are parts that the Nazis could take,areHeidegger could take, and parts that resisted Heidegger: whIch"stronger" than Heidegger's thought. The openne ss of the NIetz che-textfe l does not prevent me at the same time-far from it-from knowmg,.ing, and recalling that this multiplicity has a singulari to It; that, despIteeverything, it carries the name and pseudonyms of NI tzsche, that therehas been an event called, among many other names, Nzetzsche. I am con cerned to reflect on the historical-theoretical possibil ity of this singularbe.toprovedhasitity, however open and chaotic (in the positive sense)I will now turn more explicitly to the ethical im "de plications of Nietzsche's "destruction" of the estern traditi n. Thisforthat,gIVenvaluesofatIonstruction" always already implies a re-evaluheNietzsche, science is a reactive evaluation of life. In The Will to PowerQUESTIO N FOUR: notes,My insight: all the forces and drives by virtue of which life a d growth exist lieunder the ban of morality; morality as the instinct to deny life. One must de stroy morality if one is to liberate life.2In a gesture that is in part the same as his reduction of truth to met phor,Nietzsche's Genealogy ofMorals performs this destruction of moralIty byascribing all ethical ideals to a reactive force hostile to life: what has al .ways been understood as morality is either immoral or uses Immoralmeans to attain its own end. In this sense morality has never been, nevertaken place, and it is ultimately derived as a set of reactive affects fro the will to power. At the end of your readings of Levi-St:a ss (m,"Violence of the letter: From Levi-Strauss to Rousseau In OfGrammatology), having deconstructed Levi-Strauss's opp sition betweenwriting and speech, you remark: "There is no difference WIthout th pres .ence ofthe other but also, and consequently, without absence, dissImu a tion, detour, difference, writing. Arche-writing is the origin of moralIty 223as of immorality. The nonethical opening of ethics. A violent opening. Asin the case of the vulgar concept of writing, the ethical instance of vio lence must be rigorously suspended in order to repeat the genealogy ofmorals."3 First, to what extent does Nietzsche's reduction of morality tolife prevent him from thinking the necessity of law of which you havespoken about at length (for example, "Before the Law") and, therefore,from thinking the "prescriptive" modality of his own text? Second, inwhat ways does your final call to a repetition of the genealogy of morals(although the essay is already engaged in this repetition) differ fromNietzsche's enterprise, explicitly concerning the question of violence?SO as not to repeat several of your arguments, let me tacklequestion four head-on. I am very unsure that, when Nietzsche speaks ofa destruction of morali ty, he is speaking against any law whatsoever. I be lieve there to be a relation in Nietzsche to the law-not, obviously, whatone calls "the moral law" -that takes the form of a step back behind theethical to explain it. I would call this gesture of thought arche-ethical. Themove can be found in Heidegger, in his analyses, for example, ofGewissen, Bezeugung, and Schuldigsein in Being and Time, which concerna pre-ethical, pre-moral, pre-juridical conscience. Just as Heidegger at tempts to return to an instance or space of originarity that precedes theethical and thereby gives an account of it, so Nietzsche's genealogy ofmorals can be seen as the effort to get behind the moral and the political.Qua "genealogy, " Nietzsche's gesture cannot fail to reaffirm or promisesomething that can be called arche-ethical or ultra-ethical. This "some thing" is of the order of the law or the call [appe ; without it, genealogywould be impossible. The critique of the ruse of life is, in fact, carried outin its name. I am not j ust referring, then, to a possible reading ofNietzsche in terms of law: The law of which I speak is constitutive ofNietzsche's destruction of morality in the first place.When, for example, Nietzsche speaks of the prejudices of philoso phers, when he espies the ruse of life behind each philosopher, he mustset up his analysis under the sign of truth, no longer in the sense ofadequatio or aletheia, but in the sense of an opening to the law of truthor to the truth of law. This law-another name for which is eternalreturn-is the same thing as reaffirmation . Nietzsche's so-called destruc tion of morality is, consequently, far from being a destruction of law. Onthe contrary, Nietzsche's genealogy of morality implies an affirmation ofJ.D. :

2 24Nietzsche and the MachineT H I N K I N G AT I T S L I M I T Slaw, with all the attendant paradoxes that being-before-the-Iaw implies.Whatever these paradoxes, there is always law [il y a de la loi] . The law,or this "must," can, indeed, be read in all the prescriptive modalities ofNietzsche's discourse. When he speaks of the different hierarchies of forceand of difference of force, there must also be law. The reversal of valuesor their hierarchical ordering presupposes law-hence the foolish sim plicity of aligning Nietzsche's thought with relativism. T res ond t?,your question fully, we would need to turn to the problematIc of ,value,to Heidegger's critique of value in the thought of Nietzsche and ofothers-but an interview is not the place to do that.1would like to insist on the relationship you are making be tween the law, affirmation, and promise, to chart some important dis tinctions within what is often called contemporary French thought. Formany readers of Nietzsche-with or without Heidegger-Nietzsche re duces the question of ethics to that of life. To do so, he has to return thequestion of ethics to a history of morality, although this history of moral ity is ultimately underpinned nonhistorically by a hierarc y of f rce s or.puissances. Foucault follows the "Nietzschean" path of hlstor .l l atlOn,.actively forgetting the problem of law which, as a happy pO Slt lSt, he.cannot consider methodologically. You showed very early on In CogltOand the History of Madness" the aporias to which such a path leads.Although the essay does not concern Nietzsche's philosop y explici l!,your reading of Foucault's inability to reduce the logos to hlstory antIC1pates what you have just said on the "method" of genealogy. As forDeleuze and early Lyotard-I am comparing those of you who have rep resented, for many, a "corpus" of thought-the name of Nietzsche is ob viously not neutral since it has often served as one important thread thatgathers you into this corpus; they follow the "Nietzsche n" pat of force.By doing so, they certainly prove to be more phllosophlcal than.Foucault, but they seem equally to avoid, even denegate the problematIcof law. Hence their respective readings of force in terms of energy andintensity. For you, it always seemed to be more complicated: likeDeleuze, you argue (in your early essay "Force and Signification") thatforce in Nietzsche is always a difference between forces, you show thatthis difference cannot be historicized; but you also argued at the end ofthat essay-and what you have just said 1 believe to be a radicalizationof your earlier argument-that force and law are inextricable. Could youR. B . :225speak more of this complexity in terms of what you are calling today thepromise?J . D . : Take, as an example, the passage in On the Genealogy ofMoralswhere Nietzsche says, to gloss:"Up to now philosophers have always believed-and this prejudice constitutesthem-in the logic of opposition or contradiction, that two contradictory thingscannot get along with each other-hence the contradiction or dialectic, whichwill try to reconcile these contraries.Now, however, philosophers must not onlylearn to welcome contradiction as such, learn to understand that contradictionis not really contradictory ; we must also come to accept a logic of 'perhaps' inwhich the so-called contradiction is neither this nor that, but perhaps somethingelse.This logic concerns chance and the future.The future can only be of the na ture of 'perhaps,' so philosophy has never been able to accept the future."At this point Nietzsche announces a philosopher of the future, aphilosopher of "perhaps," saying that philosophers have been like this orthat up to now, but that soon there will come a new philosopher-andthis is what he means by "new"-who will think the "perhaps" danger ously ("this dangerous perhaps," he calls it) . This example-there aremany others-shows that Nietzsche's demolition, his reversal of all val ues, his critique and genealogy are always made in the name of a futurethat is promised. The promise does not come over and above the critique,as a post-face at the end. The promise inspires the critique in the firstplace. This new philosopher is already there, already announced throughthe way in which Nietzsche presents himself, even in his most hubristicand hyperbolic moments. The presentation shows that he partakes of thepromise himself, that the promise is not something that one hears fromelsewhere; like all promises, it must be assumed. For a promise to be as sumed, someone must be there who is sensitive to the promise, who isable to say, "I am the promise, 1 am the one to promise, 1 am the one whois promising, and 1 am promising the coming of a new philosopher." Thismeans that the one who is promising is already the promise or is almostalready the promise, that the promise is imminent. This reflectionupon imminence-the category of imminence together with that of"perhaps"-is what bears this promise. 1 am not using the term promise inthe sense that Heidegger would use it, that of a god who would come to saveus, but in the sense of the promise that here 1 am, that what 1 am doing, 1am doing here, in this text here, saying performatively what 1 am saying.

T H I N K I N G AT I T S L I M I T SThere is a promise, then, in the very move of genealogy, in its mostdestructive, "negative" moments, and this promise has to be attended to,has to be theorized as far as possible. Only in this way can its effects benegotiated in an interesting manner. These effects are everywhere. Take,since you referred to it, Nietzsche's analysis of force as the difference be tween forces. The analysis, notably in On the Genealogy ofMorals, is al ways commanded by an attention to a possible reversal in the logic en gaged with. Nietzsche is fascinated (intrigued and alarmed) by the wayin which reactivity causes the weakest to become the strongest, by thefact that the greatest weakness becomes stronger than the greateststrength. This is the case with Platonism, Judaism, and Christianity.This law of inversion is, of course, what makes the promise just as eas ily very strong as very weak, very strong in its weakness. As soon as thereis reversibility, this principle of invers

Nietzsche and the Machine RB.: It has been an insistent point on your part, informing the read ing strategy of each of your engagements with Nietzsche's philosophy, that there is one truth to Nietzsche or to Nietzsche's text. Yo ur relations to Nietzsche distinguish themselves explicitly fr om those of Heidegger, which

Related Documents:

Silat is a combative art of self-defense and survival rooted from Matay archipelago. It was traced at thé early of Langkasuka Kingdom (2nd century CE) till thé reign of Melaka (Malaysia) Sultanate era (13th century). Silat has now evolved to become part of social culture and tradition with thé appearance of a fine physical and spiritual .

May 02, 2018 · D. Program Evaluation ͟The organization has provided a description of the framework for how each program will be evaluated. The framework should include all the elements below: ͟The evaluation methods are cost-effective for the organization ͟Quantitative and qualitative data is being collected (at Basics tier, data collection must have begun)

Nietzsche’s Thus Spoke Zarathustra, Charles Bambach Nietzsche’s Beyond Good and Evil, Daniel Conway Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of Morality, Robert Guay Nietzsche’s The Case of Wagner and Nietzsche Contra Wagner, Ryan Harvey and Aaron Ridley Nietzsche’s Twilight of the Idols, Vanessa Lemm Nietzsche’s The Anti-Christ, Paul Bishop

̶The leading indicator of employee engagement is based on the quality of the relationship between employee and supervisor Empower your managers! ̶Help them understand the impact on the organization ̶Share important changes, plan options, tasks, and deadlines ̶Provide key messages and talking points ̶Prepare them to answer employee questions

Dr. Sunita Bharatwal** Dr. Pawan Garga*** Abstract Customer satisfaction is derived from thè functionalities and values, a product or Service can provide. The current study aims to segregate thè dimensions of ordine Service quality and gather insights on its impact on web shopping. The trends of purchases have

On an exceptional basis, Member States may request UNESCO to provide thé candidates with access to thé platform so they can complète thé form by themselves. Thèse requests must be addressed to esd rize unesco. or by 15 A ril 2021 UNESCO will provide thé nomineewith accessto thé platform via their émail address.

Chính Văn.- Còn đức Thế tôn thì tuệ giác cực kỳ trong sạch 8: hiện hành bất nhị 9, đạt đến vô tướng 10, đứng vào chỗ đứng của các đức Thế tôn 11, thể hiện tính bình đẳng của các Ngài, đến chỗ không còn chướng ngại 12, giáo pháp không thể khuynh đảo, tâm thức không bị cản trở, cái được

ASME A17.1 / CSA B44 (2013 edition) Safety Code for Elevators and Escalators ASME A18.1 (2011 edition) Safety Standard for Platform Lifts and Stairway Chairlifts . 3 Other codes important to conveyances adopted through state codes or as secondary references include the following: ASME A17.6 (2010 edition) Standard for Elevator Suspension, Compensation and Governor Systems ASME A17.7 / CSA B44 .