DOCUMENT RESUME ED 357 611 FL 021 159 AUTHOR Tuggy,

2y ago
39 Views
2 Downloads
829.76 KB
51 Pages
Last View : 3d ago
Last Download : 3m ago
Upload by : Macey Ridenour
Transcription

DOCUMENT RESUMEED 357 611AUTHORTITLEPUB DATENOTEPUB TYPEEDRS PRICEDESCRIPTORSIDENTIFIERSFL 021 159Tuggy, DavidThe Antigone Constraint.8051p.; In: Daly, John P. and Daly, Margaret H., Eds.Work Papers of the Summer Institute of Linguistics,University of North Dakota Session, Volume 24; see FL021 158.ReportsResearch/Technical (143)MF01/PC03 Plus Postage.*English; *Grammar; *Linguistic Theory; Nouns;*Structural Analysis (Linguistics); *Syntax*Antigone ConstraintABSTRACTThis paper presents a class of sentences that certainsyntactic rules of English would be expected to produce, but that arenot grammatical. The sentences all involve the raising of asentential Noun Phrase (NP) and the subsequent application of somesyntactic rule to that senential NP. A constraint, referred to as theAntigone Constraint, is proposed to explain the ungrammaticality ofthese sentences that prohibits two-storey rules from applying toclauses that have been raised. Evidence is given that the Englishrules of Subject-to-Subject-Raising, Subject-to-Object-Raising,Equi-NP Deletion, Extraposition, acid Non-Subject Raising should beprohibited from applying to certain structures that meet theirstructural descriptions. ********************:*****Reproductions supplied by EDRS are the best that can be madefrom the original ******************************

AThe Antigone ConstraintDavid Tuggy0. Introduction1. Arguments for Constraint A1.1 The argument from Subject-to-Subject Raising (SSR): Constraint A1.2 An argument from obligatoriness1.3 The argument from Subject-to-Object Raising (SOR)1.4 The argument from Non-Subject Raising (NSR)and Equi-NP Deletion (Equi)2. A counter-proposal considered (the Complementizer Hypothesis)2.1 The CH can account for the data so far2.2 The CH duplicates mechanisms2.3 Even for-to clauses obey Constraint AJ. Constraint A is the Antigone ConstraintThe argument from SSR and Extraposition (Extr)3.13.2 Another argument from obligatoriness23.3 The argument from SOR and Extr3.4 Other arguments from Extr3.5 The argument from SOR and Equi3.6 The argument from SOR and NSR3.7Conclusion4. The definition of the Antigone Constraint4.1 Antigonal configurations and Antigonal clauses4.2 Cases of rules affecting Antigonal configurations:the Antigone ConstrrAnt refined4.3 The definition of Antigonal configurations refined5. Conclusion0.IntroductionIn this paper I will present a class of sentences that certain syntacticrules of English would be expected to produce, but which are ungrammatical.These sentences all involve the raising of a sentential NP and the subsequentTo explain theapplication of some syntactic rule to that sentential NP.ungrammaticality of these sentences, I propose a constraint called the AntigoneConstraint,1 which prohibits two-storey rules from applying to clauses whichhave been raised.2"PERMISSION TO REPRODUCE THISMATERIAL HAS BEEN GRANTED BYU.S. DEPARTMENT OF EDUCATIONOffice of Educational Rsearch and ImprovementEDUCATIONAL RESOURCES INFORMATIONCENTER (ERICI49fhis document has been reproducedr-\--asreceived from the person or organizationoriginating it0 Minor changes have been made to improvereproduction qualityPoints of view or opinions stated in this document do not necessarily represent officialTO THE EDUCATIONAL RESOURCESINFORMATION CENTER (ERIC)OE RI position or policy

21.1.1Arguments for Constraint AThe argument from SSRA familiar rule has been proposed for English known as Subject-to-SubjectThe structural description of SSRRaising (SSR) (Rosenbaum 1967, Postal 1974).requires that, if it is to apply, the sentence to which it is to apply have asentential subject, and the main verb of that sentence be one that governs SSR.If these conditions are met, SSR can apply to raise the subject of the embeddedSSR applies, as governed byclause to become the subject of the matrix clause.the verbs be likely and seen, in the derivation of sentence (2) from thestructure underlying sentence (1), and in the derivation of (4) from thestructure underlying (3).3(1)(2)(3)(4)1.1.1That the White Knight will fall is likely.The White Knight is likely to fall.(*)That poor Bill always gets into trouble seeas.4Poor Bill seems to always get into trouble.Two derivationsSSA- governing verbs like seen and be likely can have as their subjectsWhen SSR applies in suchsentences that themselves have sentential subjects.cases, the sentential subject of the lower verb is raised to become the subjectThus SSR can apply on the So cycle of tree (5), producingof the higher verb.tree (6) and sentence (6).5(6) That the White Knight will fall seems to be likely.(7) The White Knight seems tu be likely to fall.Tree (6)sobTree (5)IMO ilia.11111111MINNI.0VPNPI11S/// 1 ,S2VseemVNPthe WhiteKnightVP1ISIseem2.,,be likelyVPfalltheWhiteKnightfallelikely

TheTree (6) apparently fulfills the structural description for SSR.question arises as to whether SSR can indeed apply to it. If SSR is applied,tree (7) results, and the corresponding sentence (7) is certainly grammatical.However, there is another possible derivation for (7), which involves SSRapplying on the Si cycle of tree (5), governed by be likely, producing tree (8).This tree will then be changed by SSR on the S0 cycle into a tree essentiallylike tree (7).6Tree (F)Tree (7)asoIthe WhiteKnightNPVPS1seemfallNPseemelikelyNrlfallthe White beKnightlikelyThus (7) could be produced in either of two ways: either by SSR applyingtwice on the S0 cycle, converting tree (5) to tree (6) and thence to (7)(Derivation I), or by SSR applying on two cycles, converting (5) to (8) andthence to (7) (Derivation II).1.1.2Derivation I should be prohibitedAs far as I know, there is no argument against permitting Derivation II.However, I would like to argue that derivations like Derivation I, deriving (7)via (6), should be proscribed because they produce wrong sentences in certaincases and are never,sentences.to my knowledge, necessary to produce grammaticalThe argument is as follows:iWhen, in a structure like tree (5), the Si verbSSR,one that does not permita derivation like Derivation II above is, of course, not possible.However, if derivations like Derivation I are permissible, one would expect thatJ structure corresponding to (7) would still be derivable.In fact, suchstructures are ungrammatical.Be a foregone conclusion is, as (9) and (10) indicate, one of the class ofverbs which do not permit SSR even though they may have a sentential subject.That the White Knight will fall is a foregone conclusion.(10) *The White Knight is a foregone conclusion to fall.(9)Consider trees (11) to (13) (sentences (12) and (13)).

4Tree (12)Tree (11)SVPNPiI.7.SseemVP./-----iS2NP1i1NPVPNP-----.be a foregoneconclusionVPseemS2./.--NPVP./Nthefallbe aforegoneconclusionIWhiteKnightfallKnightTree (14)Tree (13)0\\the WhiteKnightseembe a foregoneconclusionNPVPS,seemFr/VPe whiteKnightfalltie aoregoneconclusion(12) That the White Knight will fall seems to be a foregone conclusion.(13) *The White Knight seems to be a foregone conclusion to fall.These structures are directly parallel to (5)-(7), but with the SSR-prohibitingverb be a foregone conclusion substituted for the SSR-governing verb be likely.(14), the parallel to (8), is underivable because in order to derive it, SSRwould have to apply on the S1 cycle of tree (11), which would violate theprohibition against SSR with be a foregone conclusion. Thus (13) cannot bederived by a derivation parallel to Derivation II.However, if a derivationparallel to Derivation I is available to it, we should expect (13) to begrammatical.The crucial fact is that it is not grammatical.What is more,this same pattern of behavior apparently holds for all other sentences likethese: no matter what SSR-governing verbs are substituted for be a foregoneconclusion, the sentences parallel with (6), (7) and (12) are grammatical, butthose which parallel (13) are always ungrammatical.

Constraint A will do it1.1.3These facts must be accounted for.It seems clear that the point wherethings go wrong in the derivation is in the change from a structure like (12) toSo we need to block that step. One possible way to do this isone like (13).tochange the structural description of SSR to preclude its applicationtostructures like tree (12), perhaps by specifying that the SSRgoverning verb notbe followed by an infinitive phrase.8 However, as we will show later, similarchanges would have to be made in the structural descriptions of other rules suchThis would constitute an unnecessary duplication ofas SOR, Equi, and Extr.mechanisms, and Occam's razor9 would force us to look for a general constraintthat would accomplish the same puri.me. Several such constraints seem possible;I recommend two for your consideration at this point:Two Versions of Constraint AThe One Shot ConstraintRules may not apply more than once per cycle.The Antigone ConstraintRules may not affect clauses which have been raised.(The formulations given above are preliminary and need some adjustments andThe choice between these two versions of the constraint willclarifications.)Either version will give the right results; I knowbe discussed in section 3.of no case in which either (as correctly defined) must be violated.1 Meanwhilelet us assume that such a constraint exists and refer to it as Constraint A.Constraint A will star sentences like (13), claiming that the only possiblederivation for them would involve SSR on the S1 cycle, in despite of the factThis makes the intuitively right claimthat the S1 verbs do not permit SSR.that (10) and (13) are ungrammatical in the same way, and that (2) and (7) aregrammatical for the same reason, namely that be likely, in contrast to be aforegone conclusion, governs SSR.1.2An argument from obligatorinessCertain SSRgoverning verbs require that SSR apply.as (15) and (16) indicate.Tend is such a verb,(15) (*) That beating Time angers his tends.(16) Beating Tine tends to anger his.1.2.1Obligatoriness requirements for SSR are sometimes suspendedConsider sentences (17) and (18), which parallel (6) and (7), and (19) and(20), which garallel (12) and (13).

6(17)(18)(19)(20)That the Unicorn will win tends to be likely.The Unicorn tends to be likely to win.That the Unicorn will win tends to be a foregone conclusion.*The Unicorn tends to be a foregone conclusion to win.The structure corresponding to (17) and (19) fulfill the structural descriptionfor SSR governed by tend. Every model that I know of for administeringobligatoriness constraints like that on tend says in effect that an obligatoryrule must apply to any tree available todescription.) 1itthat meets its structuralThis means that, if SSR is in principle allowed to apply to (17)and (19), it should be required to apply to them, just as it is required toapply to (15). We have, in other words, to explain not only the fact that (20)is ungrammatical (that was our task in the last section), but also the fact that(17) and (19) are grammatical when we would have expected them to be starred bythe obligatoriness requirement on tend-governed SSR. And, once again, the samepattern holds when other SSR-requiring verbs are used instead of tend.1.2.2Constraint A predicts thisTo account for these facts we could, of course, complicate the mechanismfor administering obligatoriness requirements by introducing a constraint(unconstraint2) which would state that if an obligatory rule has applied atleast once as governed by the verb in question the obligatoriness requirement isYou might call itsatisfied even if the structural description is still met.the One-shot-is-all-you-need Condition.However, the independently neededConstraint A, by guaranteeing that you cannot apply SSR to structures like thoseThusof (17) and (19), renders it unnecessary to state that you need not.Constraint A predicts the suspension of the obligatoriness requirement in justthe necessary cases.Thus, positing Constraint A saves us from having to complicate ourstatement of obligatoriness.of Constraint A.1.3This provides another argument for the existenceThe argument from SORAnother well-known syntactic rule of English is Subject-to-Object Raising(SOR) (Postal 1974)12 whose structural description requires that the sentence towhich it is to apply have a sentential object and that the main verb of thesentence be one that governs SOR.If these conditions are met, SOR can apply toraise the subject of the embedded clause to become the object of the matrixSOR applies, as governed by the verb believe, in the derivation of (22)clause.from (21).(21) Alice didn't believe that the Queen was 101.(22) Alice didn't believe the Queen to be 101.

71.3.1SOR data like the SSR dataBe likely and be doubtful contrast in that be likely permits SSR, whereasbe doubtful prohibits it. Sentences (23) to (26) illustrate this fact.(23)(24)(25)(26)That the Queen was 101 wasThe Queen was likely to beThat the Queen was 101 was*The Queen was doubtful tolikely.101.doubtful.be 101.SOR-governing verbs like believe can have as their objects sentences thathave sentential subjects.When SOR applies in such cases, the sententialsubject of the lower verb is raised to become the object of the higher clause.Thus SOR can apply on the So cycle of trees (27) and (31), producing trees (28)and (32) elievedbelievedbelievedbelievedthat that the Queen was 101 was likely.that the Queen was 101 to be likely.lithe Queen to be likely to be 101.that the Queen was likely to be 101.(31)(32)(33)(34)Alice believed that that the Queen was 101 was doubtful.Alice believed that the Queen was 101 to be doubtful.*Alice believed the Queen to be doubtful to be 101.*Alice believed that the Queen was doubtful to be 101.Trees (27) and (31) and their derivatives differ only in that the first grouphave the SSR-governing be likely as the S1 verb, whereas the second group haveTrees (28) and (32) fulfillbe doubtful, which does not permit SSR to apply.If SOR is allowed to apply, (29) and (33)the structural description for SOR.Sentence (29) is grammatical, but it can be derived by another route,result.If SSR is applied on the S1 cycle to treewithout applying SOR to tree (28).(27), a tree corresponding to (30) can be derived, and application of SOR on theThus application of SOR toSo cycle to that tree will produce sentence (29).structures like trees (28) and (32) is not necessary for the derivation of (29).Sentence (33), however, is ungrammatical.It has no -Iternate derivationavailable to it; (34), which parallels (30), is underivable because in order toderive it one would have to apply SSR on the S1 cycle, as governed by beThus, if we can block SOR from applying todoubtful, which does not permit SSR.structures like (28) and (32), we will permit the good sentence (29) and starthe bad sentence (33).

8Tree (28)Tree (27)SnNPNPVAliceNPbe likely1AlicebelieveS,NPV1IbelieveNP 1be likelyVPbe 101the QueenTree (32)Tree 2NPNPSbe doubtful:;:tifeeNPthe QueenP1ou t u

9Tree (29)12111011111SAliceVbe likelyNPbelievebe 101eenTree (33) mSAlice VIPbelieveadoubtfulbe 101eenAs was the case with SSR examples, these examples do not stand alone.Nomatter what SORgoverning verb is substituted for believe, or what SSRprohibiting verb is substituted for oe doubtful, although sentences parallelwith (28), (29) and (32) are grammatical, those which parallel (33) areungrammatical.1.3.2Constraint A accounts for thisThese facts must be accounted for. Again, we could change the structuraldescription of SOR so that it would not apply to structures like tree (32), butto do so would be duplicating the mecnanism needed to account for the SSR case.However, Constraint A, in either version, will do the job, without entailing anyfurther complication of the syntactic mechanism.The One Shot version wouldstar (33) because SOR must apply twice on the Sn cycle in order to derive it,and the Antigone version would star it because SOR would have to apply to theraised clause S2 in order to derive it.Either way, (33) will be starred.These data, then, constitute further evidence for the existence of Constraint A.Constraint A will star sentences like (33), claiming that the only possiblederivation for them would involve SSR on the S1 cycle, in spite of the fact thatthe S1 verbs do not permit SSR.This makes the intuitively right claim that(33) and (26) are ungrammatical in the same way, and that (29) and (24) arenamely that be likely, in contrast to begrammatical for the same reason,doubtful, governs SSR.

101.4The argument from NSR and EquiThe syntactic rule of EquiNP Deletion (Equi) deletes an NP in an embeddedItclause coreferential to an NP in its mother clause (Rosenbaum 1967).triggeredbythenominaltheapplies, as governed 17y the verb be pleasant andWalrus in the upper clause, in deriving (.36) from (35).(35) (*) For Usti to eat the Oysters was pleasant for the Walrusi.(36) To eat the Oysters was pleasant for the Walrus.(35) is ungrammatical because Equi is required to apply with be (un)pleasant.Be (un)pleasant governs another rule which has been called Tough Movement,Object Raising, or NonSubject Raising (NSR) (Rosenbaum 1967:107; Postal1971:27-28; Perlmutter and Soames 1979:240-250).NSR applies to derive (37)from (36).(37) The Oysters were pleasant for the Walrus to eat.The structural description of NSR demands that the sentence to which it is toapply have a sentential subject. Berman (1974:271-273) claims that NSR is not agoverned rule, but that any verb with the appropriate structural schema will do.In addition it has been claimed that NSR cannot apply unless the subject clauseis itself subjectless, usually (if not always) because of the action of Equi, aswas the case with (36) (Chomsky 1973:240: Berman 1974:264-271; Perlmutter andThis constraint explains why (39) cannot be derived fromSoames 1979:502-511).(38), and why in (40) the unspecified person(s) who ate and who experienced theunpleasantness must be the same.(38) For the T4alrus to eat the Oysters was unpleasant for them.(39) *The Oysters were unpleasant for thee for the Walrus to eat.(40) The Oysters were unpleasant to eat.When these conditions are met, NSR raises a nonsubject NP (usually anobject) from within the sentential subject to become the subject of the matrixclause.1.4.1Equi cannot apply to some sentences derived by NSRConsider the derivationally related sentences (41) to (44).(41) *For URI. to realize that hei had eaten the Oysters was unpleasant forthe Walrusi.(42) To realize that hei had eaten the Oysters was unpleasant for theWalrusi.(43) That hei had eaten the Oysters was unpleasant for the Walrusi torealize.(44) *To have eaten the Oysters was unpleasant for the Walrus to realize.

11Tree usiiNPrealize jNPheiave eatent e111PersTree (43)SoNPrealizeSNPPP2VPunpleasantfor theWalrusiheiahve-s erseatenEqui must apply to (41) on the So cycle, converting it into (42). NSR canthen apply to (42) since S1 no longer has a subject.NSR raises S2 from itsobject position to be subject of So, producing (43).Tree (43) fulfills the structural description for Equi, and since Equi isobligatory with be unpleasant we would expect it to have to apply. However, ifit does apply, the starred sentence (44) is produced.

12Tree (44) .VPNrea izeS2PPbe unpleasantVPaye eatenefor theWalrus;s ersAs was the case in the previous two sections, this pattern hLlds no matter whatEqui-and-NSR-governing verb we substitute for be unpleasant, and what Equiprohibiting verb we substitute for want.1.4.2Constraint A will account for thisIn order to account for these facts we will want to prohibit Equi fromOne way would be to change Equi'sapplying to structures like tree (43).it from working when the governing verb isstructural description to keepSince this would be duplicating thefollowed by an infinitival phrase.mechanisms needed by the SSR and SOR cases, we rule it out. Another possibilityis that we have an ordering constraint: Under a strictly ordered model, Equimust be ordered before NSR (feeding) in order to change tree (41) into (42) soThis would mean that Equi could not apply again after NSRNSR can apply.(All these applications are, of course, on the same cycle.)(counterfeeding).However, unless aThis would explain why Equi cannot apply to tree (43).strictly ordered model can be independently justified, it itself is a.:ump3ication,.ttern.tothe theory which would exist only to explain this one dataIn any case, it is not necessary to posit rule ordering here, because theseThe One Shot version of this constraintcan be explained by Constraint A.would prohibit Equi from applying to structures like tree (43) because thiswould be Equi's second shot on cycle S0, and the Antigone version would do itEither way,because Equi would be applying to a clause that had been raised.Thus, unless independent motivation can be found for(44) will be starred.positing a strictly ordered model, these data provide additional evidence forConstraint A.

131.4.3Further support for the argument from obligatorinessHere, too, if itThese data also reinforce the argument of section 1.2.were not for Constraint A, we would need a One-shot-is-all-you-need Condition onobligatoriness to explain the fact that (43) is grammatical in spite of the factthat it fulfills the structural description for Equi, and that Equi is requiredby be unpleasant.2.2.1A counter proposal consideredthe CHThe CH can account for the data so farThere is a plausible alternative hypothesis to Constraint A which willWe will call it the Complementizerexplain the data thus far presented.Hypothesis (CH).14It has two main tenets: (a) Complementizers are chosen earlyin the derivation15 on the basis of which verb commands their clauses inunderlying structure, and complement clauses keep their original complementizer(b) Rules such as SSR, SOR and Equi make crucial reference towhen raised.None of these rules will apply if the downstairs clause theycomplementizers.affect is complementized by that; they can only affect NP's in for-to clauses.If this Hypothesis could be maintained, the following claims would be madePairs of 'sentences like (1) and (2), (3) and (4), (9) andwith respect to SSR:In(10), and (15) and (16) would come from different underlying structures.each case the first (unraised) one would have a that as complementizer on thelower clause and the other would have for-to. The ungrammat4 ality of sentenceslike (10) and (15) might be due not so much to obligatoriness constraints on theverbs involved16 as to co-occurrence restrictions holding between them and thecomplementizers at the underlying level: be a foregone conclusion would not takeThese coa for-to complementizer, nor would tend take a that complementizer.occurrence restrictions would not hold for derived structures; even though thestructures corresponding to (17) and (19) would have tend commanding a thatcomplementizer, they are not starred. But the fact that the lower clause wouldbe complementized by that (and would have to be complementized by that, since itwas originally commanded by be a foregone conclusion) would be enough to preventIt would not be necessary to invokeSSR from applying to these structures.Constraint A to prevent the derivation of (20) and explain the grammaticality of1.17) and (19).The case of SOR is similar.(28) and (29) would come from different trees;(33) could not bederived from (32) because the clause "the Queen be 101" would be complementizedby that, as would be all clauses originally commanded by be doubtful. To deriveAgain, Constraint A would(33), part (b) of the CH would have to be violated.not be needed to block the derivation.(28) with a that and (29) with a for-to complementizer.And, finally, Equi would not be able to apply to (43) to produce (44)because "he have eaten the Oysters" would have a that as complementizer and nota for-to. To apply Equi would again violate part (b) of the CH.In sum, then, the crucially bad sentences (13), (20), (33), and (44) couldbe starred because their derivations would involve violations of part (b) of the

14CH, which prevent SSR, SOk and Equi from applying to that-clauses.The CH wouldalso predict the suspension of obligatoriness in the cases of (17), (19), andConstraint A would be(43), thus accounting for their grammaticality.unnecessary in each of these cases.2.2The CH duplicates mechanismsOne argument against the CH is this:the CH requires us to posit duplicatemechanisms for SSR, SOR, and Equi: all three rules must contain statementsguaranteeing that they will apply only with for-to clauses, and not with thatI have not been able to formulate a general principle to combine theseclauses.One cannot say that all rules, or all cyclic rules, or allstatements into one.two-storey rules require a for-to complementizer, because Extraposition doesnot, as the following sentences show.(45) For the Panther to eat the Owl was cruel.It was cruel for the Panther to eat the Owl.(46) That the Panther would eat the Owl was obvious.It was obvious that the Panther would eat the Owl.Thus it will be hard if not impossible tofind a general way to statetheconstraint making SSR, SOR, and Equi apply only to that-complementized clauses.And unless such a general statement can be made, independent statements willUnless there is independent reason to justifyhave to be made for each rule.this the theory with Constraint A, which has only one statement to accomplishthe same things, is preferable.2.3Even for-to clauses obey Constraint ASeveral of theVarious other arguments against the CH are possible.assumptions embodied in part (a) of the CH can be severely questioned, if notFor instance, as sentence (47) shows, a complement originallyfalsified.embedded under be a foregone conclusion may have a for-to complementizer afterraising, although part (a) of the CH would demand a that complementizer.17(47) For the Unicorn to win would tend to be a foregone conclusion.But the strongest argument for our purposes is to point out that the CH isinadequate:there exist sentences with for-to complementizers on all theembedded clauses which exhibit the same behavior as those we examined in section1.The CH incorrectly predicts that SSR, SOR, and Equi should have unrestrictedapplication in such cases, whereas Constraint A correctly predicts that they areprohibited from applying to certain sentences.For instance, the verb be natural takes a for-to complement in suchsentences as (48).Be natural does not permit SSR:from (48).(48) For the Bellman to be admired is natural.(49) *The Bellman is natural to be admired.(49) may not be derived

15When the tree underlying (48), with its for-to complementizer, is embeddedunder a verb like tend, the same pattern emerges as in the case of (9), with itsthat complementizer.(51) For the Bellman to be admired tends to be natural.(52) *The Bellman tends to be natural to be admired.Tree (51)Tree mp S/ 2for-to benaturalVP//-'---,.be naturalthe Bellman be admired/for-to NPVPthe Bellman be admiredSSR applies on the So cycle of tree (50), producing tree (51).S2 in bothtree (50) and tree (51) is complementized by for-to. If the reason SSR cannotapply to tree (12) were that to do so would involve applying to a clausecomplementized by that, as the CH claims, we should expect SSR tD be able toapply to tree (51), as its embedded clause is complementized by for-to.However, if SSR does apply, the ungrammatical (52) is produced.Constraint A,however, correctly predicts that SSR cannot apply to tree (51), either becauseit would be applying for the second time on the cycle of tend, or because itwould be applying to a raised clause. Thus Constraint A is to be preferred overthe CH because it makes the correct prediction.The same pattern holds true no matter what SSR prohibiting and for-to usingverb is substituted for be natural, or what SSR governing verb is substitutedfor tend.Thus the same argument can be made from SSR with for-to clauses aswith that clauses.As will be obvious,the argument from obligatory SSR can also beduplicated; Constraint A is necessary to explain why (51) is grammatical as wellas why (52) is not.Similarly the arguments from SOR and from NSR and Equi can be duplicatedwith sentences using only for-to clauses.To save space I will simply listrepresentative sentences and leave it to the reader to verify that they willindeed support arguments parallel to those in sections 1.3 and 1.4.

16For SOR:(53) The guests expected for for Alice to be introduced to the Puddingto be pleasant for the Queen.(54) The guests expected for Alice to be introduced to the Puddingto be pleasant for the Queen.(55) *The guests expected Alice to be pleasant for the Queento be introduced to the Pudding.For NSR and Equi:(56) (*) For htmi to suggest for himi to eat the Oysterswas pleasant for the Carpenteri.(57) To suggest for himself to eat the Oysters was pleasant forthe Carpenter.(58) For himself to eat the Oysters was pleasant for theCarpenter to suggest.(59) *To eat the Oysters was pleasant for the Carpenter to suggest.( (58))In each case the same patterns hold true no matter what other verbs similar inrule governance and for-to usage are substituted for expect, be pleasant, andsuggest.I conclude that Constraint A is to be preferred over the CH to account forthe data so far presented, both because the CH involves unnecessary duplicationand because it cannot account for the ungrammaticality of sentences like (52),(55), and (59), nor for the grammaticality of sentences like (51) and (58).Constraint A accounts for the same data and more, and does it more simply.3.3.1Constraint A is the Antigone ConstraintThe argument from SSR and ExtrAnother well-known rule of English is Extraposi

J. Constraint A is the Antigone Constraint. 3.1. The argument from SSR and Extraposition (Extr) 3.2. Another argument from obligatoriness2. 3.3. The argument from SOR and Extr. 3.4. Other arguments from Extr. 3.5. The argument from SOR and Equi. 3.6. The argument from SOR and NSR. 3.7. Conclusion. 4. The definition of the Antigone Constraint. 4.1

Related Documents:

CONTACTS OF CHURCHES IN CYPRUS 1) The GREEK ORTHODOX CHURCH Holly Archbishopric of Cyprus, Lefkosia (Nicosia) Tel: 357 22554600, 357 22554652, 357 22554648 Fax: 357 22430451, 357 22431796 Email: arxiepcyadgam@hotmail.com Website: www.churchofcyprus.org.cy

-year old sees her obstetrician about a lump in the right breast. Her mother and aunt both have a history of breast cancer. What diagnosis code(s) should be reported? a. 611.72, V10.3 c. 611.72, V18.9 b. 611.72 d. 611.72, V16.3 . 31. A 50_ -year old female visits her p

Pega 357 with Fanuc 04PC User Pre-installation Guide Amada America, Inc. Pega 357 0 e " ". Fanuc 04PC "" , 357. .

Plan View - Pega 357 with V357hs Conveyor Optional Material Support Tables Required Optional Material Support Tables Required 288.00" Maximum travel area 144" material Electrical Requirements Pega 357 230 / 460 / 3 / 60 10% 18 kVA 46 amps @ 230 / 3 / 60 VAC 23 amps @ 460 / 3 / 60 VAC Pega 357 Compressed Air Requirements 80 psi @ 2.9 ft³/min.

DOCUMENT RESUME. ED 401 611 EA 028 042. AUTHOR Barker, Sandra L. TITLE Market Trends in School Administration: The Case in. Washington State. PUB DATE 5 Apr 96 NOTE. 15p. PUB TYPE Viewpoints (Opinion/Position Papers, Essays, etc.) (120) Reports Evaluative/Feasibility (142) EDRS PRICE MFO1 /PC

ORDIN Nr. 611/138/127/2019 din 31 ianuarie 2019 pentru aprobarea modelului, conţinutului, modalităţii de depunere şi de gestionare a "Declaraţiei privind obligaţiile de plată a contribuţiilor sociale, impozitului pe venit şi evidenţa nominală a persoanelor asigurate" EMITENT: MINISTERUL FINANŢELOR PUBLICE Nr. 611 din 31 ianuarie 2019

DOCUMENT RESUME ED 357 729 IR 015 887 AUTHOR Wilkinson, David; Meyer, Allan TITLE Distributive Information Sy

DOCUMENT RESUME ED 305 027 HE 022 357 TITLE Information Technology: Making It All Fit. . The human body needs food, water and air to survive. Safety Needs. . An example of how this analogy works In computing is to examine a Payroll system. Payrollwas one of the earliest comput