Being There: Putting Philosopher, Researcher And Student .

2y ago
29 Views
2 Downloads
325.37 KB
35 Pages
Last View : 26d ago
Last Download : 3m ago
Upload by : Kairi Hasson
Transcription

REVIEW SYMPOSIABeing There:Putting Philosopher,Researcher andStudent TogetherAgainAndy Clark, Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and WorldTogether Again. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press, 1997.Pp. xix 269. US 25 HB.By C.A. HookerArevolution in cognitive science is banishing this century'stechnological conception of mind as disembodied pure thought,namely a material symbol manipulation, and replacing it withnext century's conception: mind as the organisation of bodily interaction,intelligent robotics. Here is Clark:SLOWIntelligence and understanding are rooted not in the presenceand manipulation of explicit, language-like data structures,but in something more earthy: the tuning of basic responses toa real world that enables an embodied organism to sense, actand survive . . . it is now increasingly clear that the alternativeto the disembodied explicit data manipulation'' vision of AIis not to retreat from hard science; it is to pursue some evenharder science. It is to put intelligence where it belongs: in thecoupling of organisms and the world that is at the root ofdaily, fluent action. (p. 4)# AAHPSSS, 1998. Published by Blackwell Publishers, 108 Cowley Road, OxfordOX4 1JF, and 350 Main Street, Malden MA 02148, USACopyright 2000. All rights reserved.

REVIEW SYMPOSIAAnd again:In the natural context of body and world, the ways brainssolve problems is fundamentally transformed . . . Faced withthe problem of how to get a computer-controlled machine toassemble tight-fitting components, one solution [by PureThought] is to exploit multiple feedback loops [together witha complex fitting algorithm] . . . The solution by EmbodiedThought is quite different. Just mount the assembler arms onrubber joints . . . the computer can dispense with the finegrained feedback loops [and algorithm], as the parts jiggleand slide into place as if millions of tiny feedback adjustmentsto a rigid system were being continuously computed'. Thismakes the crucial point that treating cognition as pureproblem solving invites us to abstract away from the verybody and the very world in which our brains evolved to guideus. (p. xii; embedded quote from D. Michie and R. Johnson,The Creative Computer. Penguin: 1984, p. 95.)OK, there's the broad issue in Clark's focus. It is scientificallychallenging and technically importantÐjust ask the cosmonauts inMir trying to safely dock supply ships. But is there any philosophicalsignificance to it.? Well, yes; lots. Clark continues:Might it not be more fruitful to think of brains as controllersfor embodied activity? That small shift in perspective haslarge implications for how we construct a science of themind. It demands, in fact, a sweeping reform in our wholeway of thinking about intelligent behaviour. It requires us toabandon the idea (common since Descartes) of the mentalas a realm distinct from the realm of body; to abandon theidea of neat dividing lines between perception, cognition andaction [AI's triune machine method: receive and transduce(perception), devise algorithm (intelligence), reversetransduce and execute (action)]; to abandon the idea ofan executive center where the brain carries out high-levelreasoning; and most of all, to abandon research methods thatartificially divorce thought from embodied action taking.(pp. xii iii.)The revolution in conceptual foundations, basic principles and research methods is profound, and understanding it, assessing it, evencontributing to it is the very stuff of creative, exciting philosophy.Clark has been getting ready to tackle a theme on this scale for more# AAHPSSS, 1998.Copyright 2000. All rights reserved.71

REVIEW SYMPOSIAthan a decade now.1 But where to begin? There is no neat paradigm toexamine.The idea is young scientifically, conceptually immature, technicallyand institutionally disunified. The domain covers a bewildering array ofdisciplines as diverse as robotics and Continental philosophy, artificiallife and neurophysiology, evolutionary psychology and economics, PDPcomputation and linguistics.2 The domain is overlaid with vagueintuitions (Heidegger's hammer, Merleau-Ponty's mouse), sweepinganti-AI pronouncements (Brooks' MIT robotics rubric), near-religiousdedication to specialist technologies;3 research agendas range from theconservative desire to reconstruct symbolic algorithms within the newdevices to the complete banishment of the old apparatusÐsymbols, representations, computations, the lotÐin favour of just dynamics.4 (Notthat all these folk are not pioneers.) Hurrah, I thought. I have hadsimilar leanings for years, and made my own line of approach to thisthicket through control organisation.5 My spirit rose in anticipation atwhat Clark might offer.And deliver he does. This is a magnificent synthesis of some ofthe central animating concepts and principles of the new approach;lucid, perspicuous, gloriously eclectic and illuminatingly synthetic, it is awonderfully told tale that brings the domain into focus. I can't wait toget it into the hands of my students, philosophy, psychology, controlengineering, the lot. There's an intellectual square meal for everyone init, and so many tantalising leads running off that any studentÐanyoneof ability and love of understandingÐwill find more to chase than timepermits the catching.The real strength of the book is synthesis, and its particularcontribution, to my mind, is the bringing into clearer focus some important principles heretofore scattered in different guises across variousdisciplinary practices. A good example is what Clark calls the scaffoldingprinciple: exploiting environmental order through sequential constructionand intra-communal interaction in order to augment intelligence.Termites build complex social structures operating complex materialmounds, complete with air conditioning, repair and defence services,departments of food supply and reproduction, and so onÐa cunning,remarkably city-like contrivance. But where is the central planning department, and where the grand plan for this? There isn't one. Instead,the whole is the emergent outcome of all the interactions among individual termites, each following very much simpler rules. They are little TO DO' devices, responding to simple cues with the next thing to do.Among things to do is the dropping of little balls of salivered earth nearothers, the result being the construction of the walls and arches that72# AAHPSSS, 1998.Copyright 2000. All rights reserved.

REVIEW SYMPOSIAeventually constitute the mound. As the balls pile up the termite responsealters accordingly, no longer simply piling but also walling, filling in,finishing off the surfaceÐin short, they react to their own alteration oftheir environment. Although the reactions remain simple, they result in acomplex sequence of interchanges that constitutes the step-wise creationof their magnificent cities. Their spatially and socially stratified roles onlyemerge within, and make sense within, that construction. In this waythey have scaffolded themselves from little defenceless creatures ofmeagre cognitive abilities into resilient, viable communities, their abilitiesmagnified by taking organised advantage of the constructive propertiesof earth.Sound familiar? Like cities, language, computers, and tech colleges forhuman termites? Clark explores contexts ranging from cockroaches toeconomic rationality, from robot insects' to language, to bring into focusthe common principle of scaffolding: exploiting environmental structureand our ability to actively restructure that environment so as to bettersupport and extend our natural problem-solving abilities'' (p. 32). It isfundamental to evolution which, ceteris paribus, prefers KISS solutions(Keep It Simple Stupid), because internal organisation can remain simplerand yet complex results be producedÐour whole genetic organisation andembryogenesis is a monument to the principle (though Clark doesn'tdiscuss the sub-cognitive). And it is fundamental to understanding theorganisation of intelligence. You can construct a simple photo-tropicrobot moth' by driving its left-side wheel motors from a right-side lightsensor and vice versa.6 Here the law of variation of light intensity isreflected in the crossed-wire design; such a subtle, cross-categorialexploitation of (electromagnetic) environmental order, yet producing aneffective outcome with so simple an internal design. How could youexpect to understand the principles of neuronal organisation andfunctional strategy without understanding the dynamics of body-inenvironment in this way?We are fundamentally very complexly organised moths or termites.Consider the research Clark cites showing that only in the rightinstitutional environment, constructed for the purpose, do individualsdisplay anything approaching economic rationality (cf. a termite'sbehaviour outside of a mound) but, conversely, more than 70 percent of market efficiency can be explained by traders using verysimple mindless' trading rules. (More recent experiments show thatmore complex traders, using trend-tracking rules, will only settleinto an ordered market in sufficiently slowly changing, dampedresponse markets and that they otherwise track each other's trackingtrends to produce the locally turbulent market fluctuations we currently# AAHPSSS, 1998.Copyright 2000. All rights reserved.73

REVIEW SYMPOSIAexperience.) There is a pretty discussion of language from the sameperspective, rooted in pioneers like Vygotsky, but more general and able toraise fresh pointed questions for the old innate/learned debate. Here isClark on us:These [scaffolding] strategies are especially evident in childdevelopment. Less obvious but crucially important factorsinclude the constraining presence of public language, culture,and institutions, the inner economy of emotional response,and the various phenomena relating to group or collectiveintelligence. Language and culture, in particular, emerge asadvanced species of external scaffolding designed' to squeezemaximum coherence and utility from fundamentally shortsighted, special-purpose, internally fragmented minds . . .The Rational Deliberation turns out to be a well camouflagedAdaptive Responder. Brain, body, world and artefact arediscovered locked together in the most complex of conspiracies. (pp. 32 3.)This is terrific stuffÐthe synthesis across disciplines, the ease andclarity of writing. I do not want to detract from the achievement, andespecially not its timeliness. But it is a tale so well told that it is also easy tomiss what is not said, or said too glibly. Take scaffolding: once weunderstand that creatures and their environment can enter an interactivedance that re-makes both, giving both new explicit order and organisationand perhaps higher order capacities as well, how do we specify theresulting components? What are the limits to this? When does a neworganism, superorganism or species result? What is the difference betweena termite mound, a slime mould in aggregated sporing phase and aprimate colony that has just learned a new co-operative defence trick?These are not trivial questions for a species rapidly turning its planet into asingle, wired, information-processing mound. Clark does have a shortdiscussion about one aspect of this, the leakage' of mind into theenvironment, in the last substantive sub-section of the book, but no realprinciple of individuation emerges.Perhaps there isn't one, but if there were, I think it would begin withthe key term from Clark's title for his first chapter, but which he neveranalyses: autonomous agent''. We are offered a general image' of autonomous agents: a creature capable of survival, action, and motion in realtime in a complex and somewhat realistic environment'' (p. 6). But nomore; after that there's plenty of useful description of robots designedunder this rubric, and thought provoking that is, but we learn nothingmore about autonomy itself or what role it might play in grounding74# AAHPSSS, 1998.Copyright 2000. All rights reserved.

REVIEW SYMPOSIAintelligent capacities. That something more might be in order is indicatedby Clark's own characterisation above, a curious one for someone whowants to re-unite body and mind. For, contrary to what is suggested,surely motion is among a creature's actions, not an extra item. Sure,effective movement is currently hard for us to implement in our simpleextant robot technologies; it is a fundamental capacity, and it can beimplemented pretty much independently of other capacitiesÐbut thislast does not justify its separation from other action, it just reflects ourlimited robotics; the capacity itself would not have been biologically basicif hunting and hiding were not so selectively advantageous (as witnessplants, which are still viable systems).Again, contrary to what is suggested, action is an intrinsic componentof surviving, not an additional item. An organism must so interact withits environment (and within itself) that it acquires the resources necessary for viability (for cellular repair, locomotion, heating, etc.). For thispurpose it needs perception-organisation-action-feedback cycles on whichit can obtain successful closure. You cannot meaningfully extract onecomponent from theseÐas Clark himself elsewhere insists (see e.g. p. xiii,quoted above). But getting all the necessary interacting cyclic closuresright so as to add up to a coherent creature is not simpleÐindeed, it is oneof the most profound constraints on biological organisation generally,let alone on that of intelligent systems.Clark misses this issue, but it returns to haunt him. He complains thatpurely dynamical models of mind often leave us with an impoverishedunderstanding of the adaptive role of components'' (p. 101), but in factjust this is the result of ignoring autonomy. Independently viable systemshave to be autonomous in the above sense to at least some minimaldegree. These organisational requirements provide a set of constraints,further to those imposed by environmental selection, on biologicaldynamics, constraints which are suppressed in the standard selectionistmodels. But autonomy constraints are crucial to understanding thestructure of adaptive strategies available to an organism type becausethe required modifications must be so organisationally coherent thatautonomy is preserved. These factors are key, for example, to explainingthe difference between genetic variety coupled with shallow organisationand behavioural adaptability coupled with deep organisation but geneticuniformity, as divergent adaptive strategies, the latter alone leading tointelligence. The robots Clark mentions are not autonomous, they do nothave closure over any essential function and no self-control, though theyshare some of the same general functional features as autonomous systemsand (most importantly) their construction is moving in that direction.(A clearer, if isolated, functional autonomy was actually possessed by# AAHPSSS, 1998.Copyright 2000. All rights reserved.75

REVIEW SYMPOSIAGrey Walter's 1950's turtle', which could search for and find its ownpower source, though it moved more crudely than the newer models, andplug itself in to recharge its batteries; it at least had one complete, essentialprocess closure.)I think it clear that the book cries out for an analysis of the concept ofautonomy to undergird it. And while this is not the occasion to expoundmy own views, as just hinted, I believe that autonomy is also the rightorganisational constraint on which to ground a truly embodied accountof intelligence. Very briefly, the internal organisation and control autonomy requires can be elaborated into a platform for intelligent capacities.Autonomous systems beyond some minimum level of complexity havean intrinsic tendency to adaptability, that is, to the capacity to adaptadaptations, because they must be capable of coherent sequencing andmodification of actions. And such autonomous, adaptable systems areintrinsically anticipative. Their functionalities imply that their environmental (and internal) actions anticipate responses that will support thoseproperties. Hunting is feed forward action anticipating subsequent eatingand satiation signals. Anticipative feedforward is fundamental to all selfcontrolling systems, it combines with error-corrective feedback to deliverpowerful learning and response capabilities. And thus we arrive at Autonomous, Adaptable, Anticipative systems (AAA systems), which alreadyshow all the hallmarks of intelligence. They display complex internalcontrol of anticipative response, conditionalising it on many subtle signalsand, to the degree their control architecture is coherently adaptable, theyare able to modify it and thus learn. Thus cognitive capacities aregrounded in the organisational and control capacities of AAA systems.7This is not an account of intelligence that involves a return, with Clark,to computation and representation'' as explanatorily fundamental(p. 101). Autonomy is a dynamically grounded organisational property,but it does involve, as Clark argues, going beyond mere dynamical patternformation.This is just part of the story that underlies Clark's elegant synthesisedsurface, and needs developing. There needs to be (and are) related analyses of action, semiotics for control, epistemics and error correction, semantics and off-line emulation, and so on. Some of these analyses arepartially embryonic in the book; for example, an account of semiotic signalinformation as defined by the modifications it produces (rather than by itssender, the traditional account) is implicit in note 42 to Chapter 8Ðthough the reference to control, the part I would espouse, is there cloudedby appeal to some independently characterised representation system'.Other analyses remain unnoted; for example, emulation is brieflymentioned, but its significance left undiscussed.876# AAHPSSS, 1998.Copyright 2000. All rights reserved.

REVIEW SYMPOSIANone of this is criticism in the sense of attributing blunder. One coulddispute the whole approach, but that would be to ask Clark to write adifferent book (and anyway, I am far too much in agreement with him).One could dispute mere details, but Clark's account is too balanced andclear for that to be profitable here. There is the occasional editingblemishÐredundant notes (e.g. 13 and 38 to Chapter 8) and severalmangled bibliographical entries. But overall a splendid and timely work,whatever your theoretical proclivities. Enjoy.Department of Philosophy, University of Newcastle,Newcastle, New South Wales, Australia.1. See Clark's earlier MIT Press books Microcognition: Philosophy, Cognitive Science,and parallel Distributed Processing (1989) and Associative Engines: Connectionism,Concepts, and Representational Change (1993).2. A typical recent effort is Beer et al., Biological Neural Networks in InvertebrateNeuroethology and Robotics. New York: Academic Press, 1993.3. Such as Paul Churchland's splendid neural netist, The Engine of Reason, the Seatof the Soul. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995.4. Try Mind as Motion (1995), edited by Port and van Gelder, or Smith andThelen's A Dynamics Systems Approach to the Development of Cognition and Action(1993: yes, both published by MIT Press).5. See Hooker, Reason, Regulation and Realism, Albany: SUNY Press, 1995, at thelevel of science itself as an intelligent organisation; and also papers in Topoi 11,71 (1992) and chapter 14 of W. O'Donoghue and R. Kitchener (eds) ThePhilosophy of Psychology. London: Routledge, 1996.6. See the tantalising Vehicles by Braitenberg, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1984,not mentioned by Clark.7. For some more details see Hooker, Reason, Regulation and Realism, includinganalysis of Piaget who made endogenous control explicitly central in the 1950s,and W. Christensen and C.A. Hooker in Evolution and Cognition, 3 (1997), 44.Wayne Christensen, a PhD student and member of the dynamical systemsresearch team at Philosophy, Newcastle University, has contributed assubstantially as I to the story summarised here.8. Compare his colleague Grush's nice linkage of it to representation inPhilosophical Psychology, 10 (1997), 1. Could off-line emulation be the intendedsource of Clark's representation?# AAHPSSS, 1998.Copyright 2000. All rights reserved.77

REVIEW SYMPOSIABy Gerard O'BrienPERHAPS it's a mark of the sheer vitality of the relatively young fieldof cognitive science that it is grappling with its third majorparadigm in the space of just thirty years. While the roots of thediscipline can be traced back to the 1960s, its real beginnings in the early1970s involved the application of ideas derived from conventional digitalcomputers to human cognition, spawning the now appropriately namedclassical computational theory of mind: the doctrine that cognition isa species of symbol manipulation. Then, in the mid-1980s, the fieldwitnessed its first major shake-up with the advent of neurally inspired,parallel distributed processing (PDP) computational models, whichsubstituted operations over activation patterns for symbol manipulations,and many theorists in the field started talking passionately aboutconnectionism. Now, scarcely ten years later, the field is once again intumult, this time with the arrival of dynamical systems theory, which,because it eschews the concept of representation, threatens to create aneven greater rift in the field than that which occurred betweenconnectionism and classicism.It is in this revolutionary milieu that Andy Clark's latest book BeingThere is situated. Clark rose to prominence through his advocacy ofconnectionism, with his two previous books (Microcognition and Associative Engines) containing some of the most penetrating philosophicalwork to be found on this alternative approach to the mind. But Clark,who might have expected to spend a few more years developing connectionism in a relatively stable intellectual environment, now findshimself defending it against the even newer dynamical systems vision ofcognition.Clark's response to this predicament is to preach ecumenism. Justas Microcognition argued that we shouldn't throw out all the classicalinsights as we stampede towards connectionism, Being There puts the casefor combining the embodied, embedded aspects of cognition highlightedby dynamical models, with the commitment to representation, and hencecomputation, that we find in connectionism (and classicism, for thatmatter). This is a sensible position, in my view. And there is much toadmire in Clark's latest book. He is a gifted expositor, and Being There isbrimming with detailed and entertaining discussions of the new lightthat dynamical systems theory is throwing on the role played by both thebody and the environment in shaping cognitive processes. At the sametime he doesn't shy away from providing incisive critiques of the excessesof this programme, especially when these bubble over into what Clarkterms the Thesis of Radical Embodied Cognition'', the claim that78# AAHPSSS, 1998.Copyright 2000. All rights reserved.

REVIEW SYMPOSIA embodied cognition is best studied by means of noncomputational andnonrepresentational ideas and explanatory schemes'' (p.148). His pointhere is that such radicalism is unjustified and counter-productive, invitingcompetition between dynamical and computational conceptions of cognition where progress is more likely to be achieved through cooperation(see especially Chapter 8).While there is much in Being There that I like, the nature of reviewsymposia forces the commentator to look for points of discord ratherthan concurrence, simply because disagreements are bound to moreinteresting and response-provoking. In what follows, therefore, I willfocus on the one major ecumenical theme propounded in Being Therethat I find difficult to accept. This is Clark's advocacy, especially in thethird and final part of the book, of the extended nature of the embedded,embodied mind.Talk of the mind leaking out of the brain and into the world is in theair these days. In philosophy it's primarily driven by externalist theoriesof mental content, which hold that the meaning of some mental statesis determined by the causal relations that internal brain states bear toextrinsic, environmental factors. But Clark is quite explicit that hismotivation is quite different (see especially note 23, p. 246). For him theseepage of the mind into the environment is licensed by the subtlecouplings between the brain and aspects of the environment, so emphasised by dynamical systems theory, that make it reasonable to suppose thatcertain extra-bodily resources play a constitutive role in some cognitiveoperations. This kind of extension is most plausible, he thinks, in casesinvolving the external props of written text and spoken words, forinteractions with these external media are ubiquitous . . . reliable, anddevelopmentally basic'' (p. 214). And his conclusion is that in such cases, what we commonly identify as our mental capacities may . . . turn out tobe properties of the wider, environmentally extended systems of whichhuman brains are just one (important) part'' (p. 214).Clark is well aware that, without qualification, this thesis is in dangerof foundering on the reef of common senseÐthe distinction between mymind and yours should not be allowed to collapse just because we arefound chattering on the bus'' (p. 217). So there must be principled waysof isolating those external props that become part of the mind fromthe absolutely vast number that don't. Some of the constraints Clarksuggests here are that the requisite information must be easy to accessand use'', automatically endorsed'', and originally gathered . . . by thecurrent user'' (p. 217). His favourite example is that of a notebook, whichis our constant companion, and in which we make all manner ofscribblings. The crucial point in such a case, he argues, is that the entries# AAHPSSS, 1998.Copyright 2000. All rights reserved.79

REVIEW SYMPOSIAin the notebook play the same explanatory role, with respect to the agent'sbehaviour, as would a piece of information encoded in long-termmemory'' (p. 218). It is principally this functional isomorphism'' thatlicenses his contention that our beliefs, knowledge, and perhaps othermental states now depend on physical vehicles that can (at times) spreadout to include select aspects of the local environment'' (p. 218).In making these claims about the mind's extension beyond the skin andskull, Clark is opting for one of the two traditional ways of distinguishingbetween the mental and the merely physical. One way is to suppose thatconsciousness is the mark of the mental, and hence determines the extentof the mind. But Clark thinks that conscious experience is fully explainedby the current state of the brain, so there is no basis here for any mindexpansion (see pp. 216 17). The other way, on which Clark relies, is tofocus on the property of intentionality, whereby mental states possessthe property of aboutness or, in the language of cognitive science,representational content. The mind's boundaries, according to this secondapproach, are drawn around the representational vehicles it manipulatesin the course of cognition. And so intimate is the causal commercebetween human brains and certain written and spoken words, accordingto Clark, that these external artefacts themselves constitute part of themind's representational substrate.But I'm not convinced. It's not that I object to the general criterionby which Clark seeks to include these representational vehicles in themind (namely, that they are functionally isomorphic with those thatstandardly encode information in long-term memory). The problem, asI see it, is that, at least in the context of a broadly connectionist understanding of cognition, even his best examples fail to satisfy this condition.No matter how vigorous the causal commerce between parts of my mindand information I record in a personal notebook, these external symbolsdo not have the same causal properties as the representational vehiclesresponsible for my memories. To see this, it's necessary to step backsomewhat and rehearse some of the now fairly familiar details of themind's information coding and processing capacities, as these areunderstood from a connectionist perspective.It's commonplace for theorists to distinguish between explicit andnonexplicit forms of information coding in a computational device.Representation is typically said to be explicit if each distinct item ofinformation in the device is encoded by a physically discrete object.Information that is either stored dispositionally or embodied in a device'sprimitive computational operations, on the other hand, is said to benonexplicitly represented. It is reasonable to conjecture that the brainemploys these different styles of representation. Connectionists make80# AAHPSSS, 1998.Copyright 2000. All rights reserved.

REVIEW SYMPOSIAmuch of this distinction by pointing to the two different ways in whichinformation is coded in PDP networks and hence, by extension, in thebrain's neural networks.The representational capacities of PDP systems rely on the plasticityof the connection weights between their constituent processing units. Byaltering these connection weights, one alters the activation patterns thenetwork produces in response to its inputs. As a consequence, anindividual network can be taught to generate a range of stable targetpatterns in response to a range of inputs. These stable patterns ofactivation are semantically evaluable, and hence constitute a form ofinformation coding. What is more, because these patterns are physicallydiscrete, structurally complex objects, which each possess a singlesemantic value, it is reasonable to regard the information they encode asexplicitly represented.While activation patterns are a transient feature of PDP systems, a trained' network has the capacity to

Being There: Putting Philosopher, Researcher and Student Together Again Andy Clark, Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press, 1997. Pp. xix 269. US 25 HB. By C.A. Hooker A SLOW revolution in cognitive science is banishing this century’s technological conception of mind as disembodied pure thought,

Related Documents:

The word ‘Ecocriticism’ is extensively being experienced in . a 4th-century BC Greek philosopher. 3Quotation from Protagoras of Abdera (c. 490 - c.420 BCE) . (1912 –2009) was a Norwegian philosopher who coi

Phule can be called as Modern Indian Philosopher as Descartes. Rene Descartes (1596-1650) was a French Philosopher, has been called as µthe father of Modern Philosophy¶, and is often regarded as the first thinker emphasizes the use of reason to develop the natural sciences. For him the philosophy was a thinking

This researcher will begin the literature review with an examination of financial literacy. Next, the researcher will discuss high school work experience and the effects that it has on financial knowledge. Third, the researcher will investigate financial education that exists in the school system. Finally, the researcher will discuss gender

Olympiodorus and Damascius on the Philosopher’s Practice of Dying in Plato’s Phaedo 179 of the other term. Whereas tethnanai (death in the sense of being dead) is opposed to the infinitive zēn (life in the sense of being alive), apothnēskein (the act of dying) has another opposite, the infinitive anabiōsk

The researcher only focuses on one literary work above to analyze in this thesis. Without belittling others literary works—using existentialism theory that proposed by Jean-Paul Sartre—the researcher chooses to analyze George Milton in Of Mice and Men. Because after the researcher reads the novel there was existence’s sides in the novel.

transfer of knowledge and training activities by recruiting, supervising, hosting or training a MSCA-funded researcher. . The proposal should be prepared by the researcher in cooperation with the host organisation, which is represented by the main supervisor of the proposal. The experienced researcher and the supervisor must be two different .

Los Angeles County Child Care Planning Committee 2017 Needs Assessment Technical Report Page ii Mathematica Policy Research Emily Moiduddin, Associate Director and Senior Researcher Yange Xue, Senior Researcher Elizabeth Cavadel, Senior Researcher Morgan Hobbs, Research Assistant

making formal decisions at the final “appeal” stage of our process (see page 75 for more details ) All figures relate to the financial year 2012/2013. 4 annual review 2012/2013 . Financial Ombudsman Service Financial Ombudsman Service . annual review 2012/2013 5. chairman’s foreword. Sir Nicholas Montagu . kcb. we have resolved . more cases. than in any previous year – and each of .