Lecture Notes For Introduction To Decision Theory

2y ago
22 Views
2 Downloads
433.04 KB
79 Pages
Last View : 27d ago
Last Download : 3m ago
Upload by : Kaydence Vann
Transcription

Lecture Notes for Introduction to DecisionTheoryItzhak GilboaMarch 6, 2013Contents1 Preference Relations42 Utility Representations2.1 Representation of a preference order . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .2.2 Characterization theorems for maximization of utility . . . . . .6673 Semi-Orders153.1 Just Noticeable Difference . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 153.2 A note on the proof . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 193.3 Uniqueness of the utility function . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 204 Choice Functions235 von Neumann-Morgenstern/Herstein-Milnor Theorem276 vNM Expected Utility6.1 Model and Theorem .6.2 Proof . . . . . . . . . .6.3 A geometric approach6.4 A separation argument.37373838407 de Finetti’s Theorem437.1 Model and Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 437.2 Proof . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 448 Anscombe-Aumann’s Theorem468.1 Model and Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 468.2 Proof . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 481

9 Savage’s Theorem9.1 Set-up . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .9.2 Axioms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .9.3 Results . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .9.3.1 Finitely additive measures . . .9.3.2 Non-atomic measures . . . . .9.3.3 Savage’s Theorem(s) . . . . . .9.4 The proof and qualitative probabilities.575758585859606110 Choquet Expected Utility6510.1 Capacities and Choquet Integration . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6510.2 Comonotonicity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6610.3 Schmeidler’s Axioms and Result . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6711 Maxmin Expected Utility7011.1 Model and Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7011.2 Idea of Proof . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7112 Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem7213 References752

These are notes for a basic class in decision theory. The focus is on decisionunder risk and under uncertainty, with relatively little on social choice. Thenotes contain the mathematical material, including all the formal models andproofs that will be presented in class, but they do not contain the discussion ofbackground, interpretation, and applications. The course is designed for 30-40hours.3

1Preference RelationsA subset of ordered pairs of a set X is called a binary relation. Formally, R isa binary relation on X if R X X.A binary relation R on X is— reflexive if for every x X, xRx;— complete if for every x, y X, xRy or yRx (or possibly both);— symmetric if for every x, y X, xRy implies yRx;— transitive if for every x, y, z X, xRy and yRz imply xRz.Remark 1 A binary relation that is complete is also reflexive.Proof: Given x X apply the definition of completeness for the two elements(x, y) being that x. Then xRy or yRx, and in both cases xRx. A binary relation R on X is an equivalence relation if it is reflexive, symmetric, and transitive. An example of such a relation is equality. Anotherexample is “having the same height” (on a population of people), or “havingthe same (first) first name”. More generally, the equality of any function definesan equivalence relation, and vice versa:Proposition 2 A binary relation R on X is an equivalence relation if and onlyif there exists a set A and a function f : X A such thatxRy f (x) f (y)(1)Proof: If such a set and function exist, it is straightforward to verify thatR satisfies the three conditions. Conversely, if R is an equivalence relation, onecan defineA {{y xRy } x X }andf (x) { y xRy } .To see that (1) holds, assume, first, that xRy. Then y f (x) and by symmetryalso x f (y). Further, transitivity implies that z f (x) also satisfies z f (y)4

and vice versa. Thus, f (x) f (y). Conversely, if f (x) f (y) we first notethat, by reflexivity, y f (y), hence y f (x) and xRy. The set { y xRy } is called the equivalence class of x. The set A defined inthe proof, namely, the set of all equivalence classes (which obviously defines apartition of X) is called the quotient set, denoted X/R.For a binary relation % on a set of alternatives X, we define the symmetric( ) and asymmetric (Â) parts as follows. For all x, y X,x y if x % y and y % x;x  y if x % y and (y % x) (where denotes negation); equivalently, x  yif x % y and (y x).We also use - and for the inverse of % and Â, respectively. That is,x - y is the same thing as y % x and x y is equivalent to y  x. (Note thatthe choice of the symbols is supposed to make this natural, but these are newsymbols, which denote new relations, so we need to define them.)Proposition 3 If % is transitive, then  and are transitive.Proof: To see that is transitive, assume that x y and y z, we have (x % yand y % x) as well as (y % z and z % y). The first two parts imply (bytransitivity of %) x % z, and the second — z % x, so we get x z.To see that  is transitive, assume x  y and y  z. That is, (x % y andnot y % x) as well as (y % z and not z % y). The first two parts imply x % z bytransitivity of % as above. We need to show that z % x does not hold. Indeed,assume it did. Then we would have z % x and x % y, and transitivity (of %again) would imply z % y, which is in contradiction to y  z. Hence (z % x)and x  z. 5

2Utility Representations2.1Representation of a preference orderWe say that a function u : X R represents a relation % if, for every x, y X,x%yiffu(x) u(y).That is, we want it to be the case that the relation at-least-as-desirable interms of observable preferences (%) holds between alternatives precisely whentheir utility values satisfy at-least-as-large in terms of utility numbers ( ).One can think of other notions of “representation”, for instance, requiringthat strict inequality between the utility numbers will reflect strict preferences,or that equality would match indifference. It turns out that the first two notionsare identical, and that they imply the third:Theorem 4 Let % be a complete relation on X and let there be a functionu : X R. Define(i) x % y(ii) x  y(iii) x yiffiffiffu(x) u(y) x, y Xu(x) u(y)u(x) u(y) x, y X x, y XThen (i) and (ii) are equivalent and they imply (iii) (but not vice versa).Proof: (i) implies (ii): Let there be given x, y X. Assume first thatx  y. If u(y) u(x), by (i) we have y % x, a contradiction to x  y. Hence,u(x) u(y). Conversely, assume u(x) u(y). If y % x we would have (by (i)again) u(y) u(x), which isn’t true. Hence (y % x). But completeness impliesthat x % y or y % x has to hold, and if the latter doesn’t hold, the former does.So we have x % y and (y % x), that is, x  y.(ii) implies (i): Let there be given x, y X. Assume first that x % y.If u(y) u(x), by (ii) we have y  x, a contradiction to x % y. Hence,u(x) u(y). Conversely, assume that u(x) u(y). If x % y didn’t hold, wewould have, by completeness, y  x, and then, applying (ii), u(y) u(x), acontradiction. Hence u(x) u(y) implies x % y.6

(i) implies (iii): Let there be given x, y X. Assume first that x y. Thenx % y and y % x. Applying (i) we have u(x) u(y) as well as u(y) u(x), henceu(x) u(y). Conversely, assume that u(x) u(y). Then we have u(x) u(y),which implies (by (i)) x % y, as well as u(y) u(x) which implies y % x, andx y follows. To see that (iii) is strictly weaker than (i) and (ii), take a representation uof a relation % with more than one equivalence class, and define v u. Sucha v will still represent indifferences as in (iii) but not preferences as in (i) or (ii).2.2Characterization theorems for maximization of utilityAssume that % is a binary relation on X of alternatives as above.Theorem 5 If X is finite or countably infinite, the following are equivalent:(i) % is complete and transitive(ii) there is a function u : X R that represents %.A relation that is complete and transitive is called a weak order.Proof: It is easy to see that (ii) implies (i), independently of the cardinalityof X. Indeed, if u represents %, the latter is complete because is complete onthe real numbers, and % is transitive because so is (on the real numbers).The main part of the proof is to show that (i) implies (ii). To this end,we can assume, without loss of generality, that the equivalence classes of aresingletons, that is, that no two distinct alternatives are equivalent. The reason isthat from each equivalence class of , say A, we can choose a single representativexA A. Clearly, if we restrict attention to % on { xA A X/ } (where X/ denotes the quotient set, consisting of equivalent classes of ), the relation is stillcomplete and transitive and the cardinality of X/ is finite or countably infinite.Thus, is we manage to prove that (ii) implies (i) in this restricted case (ofsingleton equivalence classes), we will have a function u : { xA A X/ } Rthat represents % on { xA A X/ }. It remains to extend it to all of X in the7

obvious way (that respects equivalence, that is, set u(y) u(xA ) for all y Aand for every A X/ ).(As we will shortly see, assuming that the equivalence sets are singletonsdoesn’t make a huge difference. However, it’s a good exercise to go over thisreasoning if it’s not immediately obvious.)So let us now turn to the proof that (i) implies (ii) when the equivalenceclasses of are singletons. Let us start with a simple proof for the finite case:assume that (i) holds, that X is finite, and define, for x X,u (x) # { y x % y }that is, the utility of an alternative x is simply the number of elements in Xthat x is at least as good as. This is like having any two alternatives compete,and count how many “victories” an alternative has. (This may remind you ofsports tournaments.)Clearly, u is a well-defined function. Also, because of transitivity, x % yimplies u (x) u (y). Moreover, if x  y, then x { z x % z } but y /{ z x % z } so that the inequality is strict, that is, u (x) u (y). Hence we haveproved that x % y iff u (x) u (y).It is easy to see that this proof doesn’t extend to the infinite case (evenif the set is countable), because the sets { y x % y } may well be infinite, andthen their cardinalities # { y x % y } are not real numbers. Moreover, even ifwe allowed the utility to take values in the extended reals, including and , we will not get a representation. For example, if we consider the rationalnumbers with the standard relation, all of then would have the same u valueof .However, one can modify the proof a bit so that it will extend to the infinite(countable) case: definingu (x) # { y x % y }we basically counted, for each x, how many y’s does it “beat”. This is as if analternative x collects “points” for its “victories” in the matches with other alter8

natives, and we assume that the points for all alternatives are equal. However,we could do the same trick with points that are not necessarily equal. Supposethat, for each y there is a “weight” αy 0. Then, definingXαyu (x) { y x% y }— if this is a real number — the proof above goes through: transitivity proves thatx % y implies u (x) u (y), and, because αx 0, x  y implies u (x) u (y).All that is left is to choose weights αy 0 such that the summation above isalways finite. This, however, can easily be done because X is countable. We cantake any enumeration of X, X {x1 , ., xn , .} and set αxn 21n . Since thePentire series n αxn converges, u (x) is well-defined, that it, it is a real numberfor every x.Let us now look at a second proof, which uses induction. We consider a enumeration of X, X {x1 , ., xn , .}. Let Xn {x1 , ., xn } be the set consistingof the first n elements of X according to this enumeration. Clearly, Xn Xn 1for all n 1 and X n 1 Xn . We define u by induction: set u (x1 ) 0 andthen, for each n 1, we are about to define u (xn 1 ) R given the definitionof u on Xn . We will prove that, according to this definition, for every n 1, ifu represents % on Xn , it will also represent % on Xn 1 , and then observe thatthis means also that u represents % on X.Observe that, when we say “u represents % on Xn ” we refer to the values ofu on Xn , which are the first n numbers defined in the proof. Formally speaking,the function u on Xn is a different function that the function u defined on Xn 1 .However, at stage n 1 of the proof we only define u (xn 1 ) without changingthe values of u on Xn , and thus there is no need to use a different notation forthe function defined on the smaller set, Xn , and for its extension to the largerset, Xn 1 .The induction step, is, however, trivial: given Xn and u that is defined on it,let there be given xn 1 . If xn 1 xi for all i n, set u (xn 1 ) mini n u(xi ) 1. Symmetrically, if xn 1  xi for all i n, set u (xn 1 ) maxi n u(xi ) 1.Otherwise, xn 1 is “between” two alternatives xi , xj that is, there are i, j n9

such thatxi xn 1 xjand, for every k n, xk º xj or xk - xj . Settingu (xn 1 ) 1(u (xi ) u (xj ))2completes the induction step.Finally, it remains to be noted that this inductive process defines u over allof X. It is very important here that in the induction step we do not re-define thevalue of u defined in previous steps, so that u on X is well-defined. In fact, whenwe recall that functions are sets of ordered pairs, the function u on X is simplythe union of the functions u defined over Xn — when we take the union over all n.To see this u represents % over all of X, consider two elements x, y X. Theyappear in the enumeration, say, x xk and y xl . Then, taking n max(k, l),we have x, y Xn , and then x % y iff u(x) u (y) because u represents % overXn . To see that the theorem, as stated, cannot generally be true if X is uncountable, consider Debreu’s famous example of a lexicographic order (Debreu, 1959):let X [0, 1]2 and (x1 , x2 ) %L (y1 , y2 ) if and only if [x1 y1 or (x1 y1 andx2 y2 )].Proposition 6 There is no function u : [0, 1]2 R that represents %L .Proof: If there were such a function, then, for every value of x1 [0, 1] therewould be an open interval of utility values,I(x1 ) (u (x1 , 0) , u (x1 , 1))(with u (x1 , 1) u (x1 , 0)) such that, for x1 y1 , I(x1 ) and I(y1 ) are disjoint(because u (x1 , 0) u (y1 , 1)). However, on the real line we can only havecountably many disjoint open intervals (for instance, because each such intervalcontains a rational number). This means that in order to get a representation of % by a utility functionwhen X is not countable we need to make additional assumptions.10

One direction to follow (again, Debreu, 1959) is to assume that the set ofalternatives X is a topological space, and require that % be continuous withrespect to this topology. For example, in the case X Rk , we define continuityas follows: % is continuous if, for all x, y X and every {xn } Rk such thatxn x, (i) if xn % y for all n, then x % y, and (ii) if y % xn for all n, theny % x.Remark 7 Assume that X Rk . Then % is continuous iff, for every y Rk ,the sets {x X x  y} and {x X y  x} are open (in the standard topologyon X Rk ).Given that definition, one may state:Theorem 8 If X Rk , the following are equivalent:(i) % is complete, transitive, and continuous(ii) there is a continuous function u : X R that represents %.We will not prove this theorem here. Rather, we follow the other direction,due to Cantor (1915), where no additional assumptions are made on X. Inparticular, it need not be a topological space, and if it happens to be one,we still will not insist on continuity of u. Instead, Cantor used the notion ofseparability: % is separable if there exists a countable set Z X such that, forevery x, y X\Z, if x  y, then there exists z Z such that x % z % y.Theorem 9 (For every X) The following are equivalent:(i) % is complete, transitive, and separable(ii) there is a function u : X R that represents %.Let us now briefly understand the mathematical content of separability. Thecondition states, roughly speaking, that countably many element (those of Z)tell the entire story. If we want to know how an alternative x ranks, it suffices toknow how it ranks relative to all elements of Z. Observe that, if X is countable,separability vacuously holds, since one may choose Z X.11

To see that the separability axiom has some mathematical power, and that itmay give us hope for utility representation, let us see why it rules out Debreu’sexample above. In this example, suppose that Z X [0, 1]2 is a countableset. Consider its projection on the first coordinate, that is,Z1 { x1 [0, 1] x2 [0, 1] s.t.(x1 , x2 ) Z} .Clearly, Z1 is also countable. Consider x1 [0, 1]\Z1 and note that (x1 , 1) Â(x1 , 0). However, no element of Z can be between these two in terms of preference, since it cannot have x1 as its first coordinate.Proof of Theorem 9As above, the discussion is simplified if we assume, without loss of generality,that there are no equivalences.We may go back to the two proofs of Theorem 5 and try to build on theseideas. The second proof, by which the values of u (xn ) were defined by inductionon n, doesn’t generalize very graciously. For a countable set, one can have aenumeration of the elements, such that each one of them has only finitely manypredecessors. This allowed us to find a value for u (xn ) for each n, so that urepresented % on the elements up to xn . However, when X is uncountable, nosuch enumeration exists. Thus, there will be (many) elements x of X that haveinfinitely many predecessors. And then it might be impossible to find a valueu (x) that allows u to represent % on all the elements up to x. (For example,assume that x  z and yn  x where we have already assigned the valuesu (z) 0 and u (yn ) 1n .)However, the first proof does extend to the general set-up. Recall that, inthe countable case, we agreed that for each y there would be a “weight” αy 0and that, given these weights, we would defineu (x) Xαy .{ y x% y }You might think that, when X is uncountable, the corresponding idea wouldbe to have an integral (over all { y x % y } for each x) instead of a sum. But12

this would require a definition of an algebra on X (which is not the hard part)and a definition of αy 0 so that the function α· is integrable relative tothat algebra (which is harder). However, these complications are not necessary:the separability requirement says that countably many elements “tell the entirestory”. Hence, we should take the sum not over all { y x % y }, but only overthose elements of Z that are in this set.Hence, for the proof that (i) implies (ii), let Z {z1 , z2 , .} and defineXX11u(x) .(2)i22izi X,x% zizi X,zi ÂxClearly u(x) R for all x (in fact, u(x) [ 1, 1]). It is easy to see that x % yimplies u(x) u(y). To see the converse, assume that x  y. If one of {x, y} isin Z, u(x) u(y) follows from the definition (2). Otherwise, invoke separabilityto find z Z such that x  z  y and then use (2).Another little surprise in this theorem, somewhat less pleasant, is how messythe proof of the converse direction is. Normally we expect axiomatizations tohave sufficiency, which is a challenge to prove, and necessity which is simple. Ifit is obvious that the axioms are necessary, they are probably quite transparentand compelling. (If, by contrast, sufficiency is hard to prove, the theorem issurprising in a good sense: the axioms take us a long way.) Yet, we should beready to sometimes work harder to prove the necessity of conditions such ascontinuity, separability, and others that bridge the gap between the finite andthe infinite.In our case, if we have a representation by a function u, and if the rangeof u were the entire line R, we would know what to do: to select a set Z thatsatisfies separability, take the rational numbers Q {q1 , q2 , .}, for each suchnumber qi select zi such that u(zi ) qi , and then show that Z separates X.The problem is that we may not find such a zi for each qi . In fact, it is evenpossible that range(u) Q .In some sense, we need not worry too much if a certain qi is not in the rangeof u. In fact, life is a little easier: if no element will have this value, we will notbe asked to separate between x and y whose utility is this value. However, what13

happens if we have values of u very close to qi on both sides, but qi is missing?In this case, if we fail to choose elements with u-values close to qi , we may laterbe confronted with x  y such that u(x) (qi , qi ε) and u(y) (qi ε, qi ) andwe will not have an element of z with x  z  y.Now that we see what the problem is, we can also find a solution: for eachqi , find a countable non-increasing sequence {zik }k such that{u(zik )}k & inf{u(x) u(x) qi }and a countable non-decreasing sequence {wik }k such that{u(zik )}k % sup{u(x) u(x) qi }assuming that the sets on the right hand sides are non empty. The (countable)union of these countable sets will do the job. In all of these representation results (Theorems 5, 8, 9), the function u isunique only up to increasing transformations. That is, if f : R R is a strictlyincreasing function, and u represents %, thenv f (u)also represents %. (In Theorem 8 one would need to require that f be continuousto guarantee that v is continuous on X, as is u. In the other two theorems wedon’t have a topology on X, and continuity of u or v is not defined. Therefore itmakes no difference if f is continuous or not.) For that reason, a utility functionu that represent % is called ordinal. Importantly, when we say that “u is ordinal”we don’t refer to a property of the function u as a mathematical object per se,but to the way we use it. Saying that u is ordinal is like saying “I’m usingthe function u, but don’t take me too literally; it’s actually but an example ofa function, a representative of a large class of functions that are equivalent interms of their observable content, and any monotone transformation of u canbe used as “the” utility function just as well. I’ll try not to say anything thatdepends on the particular function u and that would not hold true if I were toreplace u by a monotone transformation thereof, v.”14

3Semi-Orders3.1Just Noticeable DifferenceProposition 3 showed that transitivity of % implies that of . However, manyalternatives involve variables that can be thought of as continuous, and in thesecases it does not make sense to assume that is transitive due to our limitedcapacity to discern difference. In Luce’s coffee mug example, a decision makerhas preferences over coffee mugs with n grains of sugar. Not being able todiscern a mug with n grains of sugar from one with n 1 grains, one can hardlyexpect there to be strict preference. Thus, we get indifference between anytwo consecutive alternatives, but this doesn’t mean that we’ll get indifferencebetween any pair of alternatives.Indeed, Weber’s Law in psychophysiology (dating back to 1834), states thata person’s ability to discern difference between perceptual stimuli is limited. Hedefined the just noticeable difference to be the minimal increase in a stimulusthat is needed for the difference to be noticed. More precisely, if S is a level of astimulus, let S be the minimal quantity such that (S S) can be identifiedas larger than S with probability of at least 75%. Weber’s Law states that S/S is a constant, independent of S, say, λ 0. In other words, if S 0 S,the person will be able to tell that this is indeed the case (with probability of75% or more) iffS 0 S S (1 λ) SorS0 1 λSorlog (S 0 ) log (S) δ log (1 λ) 0.Inspired by this law, Luce (1956) was interested in strict preferences P thatcan be described by a utility function u through the equivalencexP yiffu(x) u(y) δ 015 x, y X.(3)

If (3) for u : X R and δ 0, we say that the pair (u, δ) L-represents P .Seeking to axiomatize L-representations, Luce considered the binary relationP (on a set of alternatives X) as primitive. The relation P is interpreted asstrict preference, where I (P P 1 )c — as absence of preference in eitherdirection, or “indifference”.1Luce formulated three axioms, which are readily seen to be necessary for anL-representation. He defined a relation P to be a semi-order if it satisfied thesethree axioms, and showed that, if X is finite, the axioms are also sufficient forL-representation.To state the axioms, it will be useful to have a notion of concatenation ofrelations. Given two binary relations B1 ,B2 X X, let B1 B2 X X bedefined as follows: for all x, y X,xB1 B2 yiff z X, xB1 z, zB1 y.Observe that, if you think of a relation B as a binary matrix, whose rowsand columns are members of X, and such that Bxy 1 iff xBy (and Bxy 0otherwise), then the concatenated relation B1 B2 precisely corresponds to the“product” of the matrices B1 and B2 is by “addition” we mean “or” (that is,1 0 0 1 1 1 1).We can finally state Luce’s axioms. The relation P (or (P, I)) is a semi-orderif:L1. P is irreflexive (that is, xP x for no x X);L2. P IP PL3. P P I P .The meaning of L2 is, therefore: assume that x, z, w, y X are such thatxP zIwP y. Then it has to be the case that xP y. Similarly, L3 requires thatxP y will hold whenever there are z, w X such that xP zP wIy.Since I is reflexive, each of L2, L3 implies transitivity of P (but not of I!).But L2 and L3 require something beyond transitivity of P . For example, if1 For a relation P X X, define P 1 to be the inverse, i.e., P 1 {(x, y) (y, x) P }.Thus, I (P P 1 )c is equivalent to say that xIy if and only if neither xP y nor yP x.16

X R2 and P is defined by Pareto domination, P is transitive but you canverify that it satisfies neither L2 nor L3.Conditions L2 and L3 restrict the indifference relation I. For the Paretorelation P , the absence of preference, I, means intrinsic incomparability. Hencewe can have, say, xP zP wIy without being able to say much on the comparisonbetween x and y. It is possible that y is incomparable to any of x, z, w becauseone of y’s coordinates is higher than the corresponding coordinate for all ofx, z, w. This is not the case if I only reflects the inability to discern smalldifferences. Thus, L2 and L3 can be viewed as saying that the incomparabilityof alternatives, reflected in I, can only be attributed to issues os discernibility,and not to fundamental problems as in the case of Pareto dominance.Looking at Luce’s three conditions, you may wonder why not require alsoL4. IP P P .The answer is that it follows from the previous two. More preciselyProposition 10 Assume that P is irreflexive. Then(i) L3 implies L4(ii) L4 implies L3(iii) L3 (and L4) do not imply L2(iv) L2 does not imply L3 (or L4).Proof: (i) Assume L3. To see that L4 holds, let there be given x, y, z, w Xsuch that xIyP zP w. We need to show that xP w. If not, we have either wP x orwIx. We argue that in either case, yP x. Indeed, if wP x, we have yP zP wP x.Recall that P is transitive by L3. Hence yP x. If, however, wIx, we haveyP zP wIx and, by L3, yP x. However, this is a contradiction because xIy.(ii) Assume L4. To see that L3 holds, let there be given x, y, z, w X suchthat xP yP zIw. We need to show that xP w. If not, we have either wP x or wIx.We argue that in either case, wP z. Indeed, if wP x, we have wP xP yP z and(since L4 also implies transitivity of P ), wP z. If, however, wIx, then wIxP yP zand L4 implies wP z. Thus, in both cases we obtain wP z, which contradictszIw.17

(iii) Consider X {x, y, z, w} and P {(x, y) , (z, w)}. L3 and L4 holdvacuously (as there are no chains of two P relations) but L2 doesn’t. (If itdid, we should have xP w because xP yIzP w — and, indeed, also zP y becausezP wIxP y.)(iv) Consider X {x, y, z, w} and P {(x, y) , (y, z) , (x, z)}. L2 holds, asP IP {(x, z)} (because xP yIyP z but there is no other quadruple of elementssatisfying this chain of relations) and, indeed, (x, z) P . However, L3 does nothold (if it did, xP yP zIw would imply xP w) nor does L4 (if it did, wIxP yP zwould imply wP z). It is an easy exercise to show that L2 and L3 are necessary conditions for anL-representation to exist. It takes more work to prove the following.Theorem 11 (Luce) Let X be finite. P X X is a semi-order if and onlyif there exists u : X R that L-represents it.We will not prove this theorem here, but we will make several commentsabout it.If we drop L3 (but do not add L4), we get a family of relations that Fishburn(1970b, 1985) defined as interval relations. Fishburn proved that, if X is finite,a relation is an interval relation if and only if it can be represented as follows:for every x X we have an interval, (b(x), e(x)), with b(x) e(x), such thatxP yiffb(x) e(y) x, y Xthat is, xP y iff the entire range of values associated with x, (b(x), e(x)), is higherthan the range of values associated with y, (b(y), e(y)).Given such a representation, you can define u(x) b(x) and δ(x) e(x) b(x) to get an equivalent representationxP yiffu(x) u(y) δ(y) x, y X(4)Comparing (4) to (3), you can think of (4) as a representation with a variablejust noticeable difference, whereas (3) has a constant jnd, which is normalizedto 1.18

3.2A note on the proofIf P is a semi-order, one can define from it a relation Q P I IP . That is,xQy if there exists a z such that (xP z and zIy) or (xIz and zP y). This is anindirectly revealed preference: suppose that xIy but xP z and zIy. This meansthat a direct comparison of x and y does not reveal a noticeable difference,and therefore no preference either. But, when comparing x and y to anotheralternative z, it turns out that x is

Lecture Notes for Introduction to Decision Theory Itzhak Gilboa March 6, 2013 Contents 1 Preference Relations 4 2 Utility Representations 6 . These are notes for a basic class in decision theory. The focus is on decision under risk and under uncertainty, with relatively little on social choice. The

Related Documents:

Introduction of Chemical Reaction Engineering Introduction about Chemical Engineering 0:31:15 0:31:09. Lecture 14 Lecture 15 Lecture 16 Lecture 17 Lecture 18 Lecture 19 Lecture 20 Lecture 21 Lecture 22 Lecture 23 Lecture 24 Lecture 25 Lecture 26 Lecture 27 Lecture 28 Lecture

Bruksanvisning för bilstereo . Bruksanvisning for bilstereo . Instrukcja obsługi samochodowego odtwarzacza stereo . Operating Instructions for Car Stereo . 610-104 . SV . Bruksanvisning i original

GEOMETRY NOTES Lecture 1 Notes GEO001-01 GEO001-02 . 2 Lecture 2 Notes GEO002-01 GEO002-02 GEO002-03 GEO002-04 . 3 Lecture 3 Notes GEO003-01 GEO003-02 GEO003-03 GEO003-04 . 4 Lecture 4 Notes GEO004-01 GEO004-02 GEO004-03 GEO004-04 . 5 Lecture 4 Notes, Continued GEO004-05 . 6

Lecture 1: A Beginner's Guide Lecture 2: Introduction to Programming Lecture 3: Introduction to C, structure of C programming Lecture 4: Elements of C Lecture 5: Variables, Statements, Expressions Lecture 6: Input-Output in C Lecture 7: Formatted Input-Output Lecture 8: Operators Lecture 9: Operators continued

10 tips och tricks för att lyckas med ert sap-projekt 20 SAPSANYTT 2/2015 De flesta projektledare känner säkert till Cobb’s paradox. Martin Cobb verkade som CIO för sekretariatet för Treasury Board of Canada 1995 då han ställde frågan

service i Norge och Finland drivs inom ramen för ett enskilt företag (NRK. 1 och Yleisradio), fin ns det i Sverige tre: Ett för tv (Sveriges Television , SVT ), ett för radio (Sveriges Radio , SR ) och ett för utbildnings program (Sveriges Utbildningsradio, UR, vilket till följd av sin begränsade storlek inte återfinns bland de 25 största

Hotell För hotell anges de tre klasserna A/B, C och D. Det betyder att den "normala" standarden C är acceptabel men att motiven för en högre standard är starka. Ljudklass C motsvarar de tidigare normkraven för hotell, ljudklass A/B motsvarar kraven för moderna hotell med hög standard och ljudklass D kan användas vid

LÄS NOGGRANT FÖLJANDE VILLKOR FÖR APPLE DEVELOPER PROGRAM LICENCE . Apple Developer Program License Agreement Syfte Du vill använda Apple-mjukvara (enligt definitionen nedan) för att utveckla en eller flera Applikationer (enligt definitionen nedan) för Apple-märkta produkter. . Applikationer som utvecklas för iOS-produkter, Apple .