THE QUESTION OF GOD - Religious Studies

2y ago
19 Views
2 Downloads
3.12 MB
378 Pages
Last View : 4d ago
Last Download : 3m ago
Upload by : Olive Grimm
Transcription

THE QUESTION OF GODThis important new text by a well-known author provides a lively and approachableintroduction to the six great arguments for the existence of God. Requiring no specialistknowledge of philosophy, an important feature of The Question of God is the inclusion of awealth of primary sources drawn from both classic and contemporary texts. With itscombination of critical analysis and extensive extracts, this book will be particularly attractiveto students and teachers of philosophy, religious studies and theology, at school or universitylevel, who are looking for a text that offers a detailed and authoritative account of thesefamous arguments. The Ontological Argument (sources: Anselm, Haight, Descartes, Kant, Findlay,Malcolm, Hick) The Cosmological Argument (sources: Aquinas, Taylor, Hume, Kant) The Argument from Design (sources: Paley, Hume, Darwin, Dawkins, Ward) The Argument from Miracles (sources: Hume, Hambourger, Coleman, Flew, Swinburne,Diamond) The Moral Argument (sources: Plato, Lewis, Kant, Rachels, Martin, Nielsen) The Pragmatic Argument (sources: Pascal, Gracely, Stich, Penelhum, James, Moore).This user-friendly books also offers: Revision questions to aid comprehension Key readingfor each chapter and an extensive bibliography Illustrated biographies of key thinkers andtheir works Marginal notes and summaries of arguments.Dr Michael Palmer was formerly a Teaching Fellow at McMaster University and HumbodltFellow at Marburg University. He has also taught at Marlborough College and BristolUniversity, and was for many years Head of the Department of Religion and Philosophy atThe Manchester Grammar School. A widely read author, his Moral Problems (1991) hasalready established itself as a core text in schools and colleges. Other publications includePaul Tillich’s Philosophy of Art (1984), the six-volume Paul Tillich: Hauptwerke/Main Works(ed., 1990), Freud and Jung on Religion (Routledge, 1997) and Moral Problems in Medicine(1999).

THE QUESTION OF GODAn introduction and sourcebookMichael PalmerLondon and New York

First published 2001 by Routledge11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EESimultaneously published in the USA and Canadaby Routledge29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis GroupThis edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2002. 2001 Michael PalmerAll rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted orreproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanicalor other means, now known or hereafter invented, includingphotocopying and recording, or in any information storage orretrieval system, without permission in writing fromthe publishers.British Library Cataloguing in Publication DataA catalogue record for this book is available from the British LibraryLibrary of Congress Cataloging in Publication DataPalmer, Michael F., 1945–The question of God : an introduction and sourcebook / Michael Palmer.p. cm.Includes bibliographical references and index.1. God—Proof. I. Title.BT103 .P35 2001212′.1—dc21ISBN 0–415–22386–5 hbk0–415–22387–3 pbkISBN 0-203-20864-1 Master e-book ISBNISBN 0-203-20876-5 (Glassbook Format)00–065304

ForJohn Heywood Thomas

CONTENTSList of illustrationsPrefaceUsing the InternetxiiixvxviiCHAPTER 1THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT1COMMENTARYIntroduction: a priori and a posteriori arguments2Anselm’s argument: stage 14Anselm’s argument: stage 27Descartes’ ontological argument9The two stages of the argument: a summary11Kant’s criticism of the ontological argument (first stage)11Kant’s criticism of the ontological argument (second stage)16The ontological argument revisited: Findlay and Malcolm19Karl Barth: a theological interpretation25Conclusion3030QUESTIONSSOURCES1 Anselm: The ontological argument312 Haight: An ontological argument for the Devil333 Descartes: The supremely perfect being354 Kant: The impossibility of an ontological proof365 Findlay: Disproof of God’s existence386 Malcolm: Anselm’s second ontological proof407 Hick: Necessary being42KEY TEXTS45BIBLIOGRAPHY45

viiiCONTENTSCHAPTER 2THE COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT48COMMENTARYIntroduction: the argument as an a posteriori proof49St Thomas Aquinas: the arguments from motion and cause50A problem of interpretation: temporal or ontological cause?52St Thomas Aquinas: the argument from contingency55Criticism (1): the principle of sufficient reason58Criticism (2): the argument from causality64Criticism (3): the concept of necessary being7275QUESTIONSSOURCES1 Aquinas: The five proofs of God’s existence752 Taylor: The principle of sufficient reason773 Hume: Objections to the cosmological argument834 Hume: The relation of cause and effect845 Kant: The impossibility of a cosmological proof87KEY TEXTS90BIBLIOGRAPHY90CHAPTER 3THE ARGUMENT FROM DESIGN92COMMENTARYIntroduction93The argument stated (1)93The argument (2): induction and analogy97QUESTIONSThe argument (3): its analogical form100Hume’s critique of the design argument104Darwin’s critique of the design argument117Post-Darwinian theories of design129The anthropic teleological argument133Swinburne’s design argument137Conclusion143144

CONTENTSSOURCESix1 Paley: The watch and the watchmaker1452 Hume: The design argument1463 Darwin: The existence of a personal God1534 Dawkins: God’s utility function1565 Ward: Darwin’s gloomy view161KEY TEXTS166BIBLIOGRAPHY166CHAPTER 4THE ARGUMENT FROM MIRACLES170COMMENTARYIntroduction171David Hume: ‘Of Miracles’172Extending Hume’s argument: McKinnon and Flew183Criticism of Hume (1): laws of nature187Criticism of Hume (2): historical evidence for miracles:Flew and Swinburne188Criticism of Hume (3): evidence of God’s activity195Criticism of Hume (4): the contingency definition of miracles:Holland and Tillich198Conclusion203203QUESTIONSSOURCES1 Hume: ‘Of Miracles’2042 Hambourger: The principle of relative likelihood2123 Coleman: Miracles and lotteries2134 Flew: Miracles and repeatability2165 Swinburne: Evidence of miracles2196 Diamond: Miracles and scientific autonomy221KEY TEXTS224BIBLIOGRAPHY224

xCONTENTSCHAPTER 5THE MORAL ARGUMENT227COMMENTARYIntroduction: objective and relative moral values228The moral argument outlined230The Euthyphro dilemma232Kant’s moral argument (1): autonomy and categorical duty235Kant’s moral argument (2): God as the postulate of moral action241Criticisms of Kant’s moral argument246Post-Kantian moral arguments: divine command theory250Conclusion: absolute moral laws without God259261QUESTIONSSOURCES1 Plato: The Euthyphro dilemma2622 Lewis: The Law of Nature2643 Kant: The existence of God as a postulate of pure practical reason2684 Rachels: God and autonomy2725 Martin: Atheism, Christian theism, and rape2766 Nielsen: Morals without God279KEY TEXTS281BIBLIOGRAPHY282CHAPTER 6THE PRAGMATIC ARGUMENT285COMMENTARYIntroduction286Pascal’s pragmatic argument: the Wager286Criticisms of Pascal’s Wager293James’ pragmatic argument: the will to believe302Summary of James’ theory of belief317Criticisms of William James317Concluding remarks324QUESTIONS325

CONTENTSSOURCESxi1 Pascal: The Wager3262 Gracely: The Devil’s offer3283 Stich: Recombinant DNA and Pascalian wagering3294 Penelhum: Criticism of Pascal’s Wager3305 James: The will to believe3326 Moore: James’ pragmatism338KEY TEXTS340BIBLIOGRAPHY340Acknowledgements: illustrationsAcknowledgements: sourcesAppendix: Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Online andThe Question of GodIndex of namesIndex of subjects344346348354356

PLATESCHAPTER 1:THE ONTOLOGICALARGUMENTCHAPTER 2:THE COSMOLOGICALARGUMENTCHAPTER 3:THE ARGUMENTFROM DESIGNCHAPTER 4:THE ARGUMENTFROM MIRACLESSt AnselmRené DescartesImmanuel KantBertrand RussellJohn HickKarl BarthManuscript page from Barth’s fides quaerens intellectum4101214232527St Thomas AquinasAristotleFrederick Copleston, SJDavid HumeCritique of Pure Reason, title page, first editionImmanuel Kant: the Königsberg statue505154657173William PaleyManuscript page from Hume’s Dialogues Concerning Natural ReligionEpicurusCharles DarwinHMS BeagleSir Charles LyellThomas MalthusMalthus requests population information for the United StatesDarwin acknowledges his debt to MalthusConclusion page of Darwin’s Origin of Species, 3rd edn, p. 514Frederick Temple96105112118118119120121124129130Hume’s Of Miracles, first editionBishop Joseph ButlerAntony FlewRichard SwinburnePaul Tillich173177185191199

xivI L L U S T R AT I O N SCHAPTER 5:C. S. LewisPlatoKant: a contemporary silhouetteManuscript page from Kant’s Opus PostumumKant: Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, title page, first editionCritique of Practical Reason, title page, first editionKant’s house in KönigsbergJohn Henry Newman231232234235238242246252Blaise PascalPensées, title page, first editionSigmund FreudWilliam JamesManuscript page from James’ ‘The Will to Believe’G. E. Moore287289300303312323THE MORALARGUMENTCHAPTER 6:THE PRAGMATICARGUMENT

PREFACEThere are many arguments for and against the existence of God, and this bookis not intended to be a compendium of them. Rather it offers a criticalassessment of what are, beyond dispute, six of the most important argumentsfor God within the Western theological tradition, and couples that analysiswith an anthology of some of the primary texts associated with them. Thereare, however, two classes of reader for whom this work is specifically designed.First, there are those who have just started a programme of study in this area,either at school or university level; and second, there are those more generalreaders who, lacking professional support, wish by themselves to gain someidea of the momentous debates and great literature that this area covers. To thissecond group I should add that this book requires no initial knowledge ofphilosophy, that technical terms are kept to an absolute minimum, and that Ihave tried, in line with some other books of mine, to make this one as ‘userfriendly’ as possible.To this end I have employed a somewhat unusual format, which I shouldexplain here. Each chapter is split into five sections: (1) Commentary; (2)Questions; (3) Sources; (4) Key Texts; and (5) Bibliography. These are, I hope,self-explanatory, with the first and third sections being the most important.The Commentary is my own summary and appraisal of the argument underdiscussion, liberally peppered with exercises and short biographies to assist thereader. The Sources are the primary texts to which I sometimes refer duringthe course of my analysis. So, for example, when examining Anselm’s ontological argument in Chapter 1, I cite Anselm’s original Proslogium, which maythen be read in the appropriate section.If the inclusion of primary sources turns this book into a rather unusualhybrid – part textbook and part anthology – it also and inevitably raises thequestion posed by any sourcebook: what to select? This is always a difficultproblem, and I am reconciled to the fact that my choices will not be to everybody’s taste. To highlight its location, an arrow is positioned in the marginopposite every source reference. Some of the sources, of course, select themselves: Aquinas’ ‘Five Ways’, Paley on design, Hume on miracles, Pascal’s Wager,and so on. To these I have added passages which, although sometimesunfamiliar, advance the argument in an interesting direction, even thoughperhaps running counter to my own in the Commentary. But that, I think, isall to the good. At any event, I believe that there is no substitute for readingprimary sources, and that it is always better to let authors speak for themselvesthan to meet them solely through the writings of others.

xviP R E FA C EFor the most part this book incorporates a series of lectures first given at theUniversity of Bristol some years ago as part of an introductory course on thePhilosophy of Religion, which makes this the second set of my Bristol lecturesthat Routledge has published. As with Freud and Jung on Religion (1997), theexperience of publication has been a problem-free pleasure, and for that I haveto thank four people: my commissioning editor Roger Thorp, my productioneditor Ruth Bourne, and my copy editor Pauline Marsh. I owe a particulardebt of gratitude, however, to Moira Taylor, my development editor, who withlimitless patience and good humour has been a constant source of constructiveideas and enthusiastic support.This book has been read in its entirety by Professor John Heywood Thomas,and I have deeply valued his many criticisms and suggestions. It is affectionatelydedicated to him as my friend and teacher for over thirty years.Michael Palmer

USING THE INTERNETOne of the extracts used in this book – Martin’s ‘Atheism, Christian Theismand Rape’ – comes from the Internet. The Internet is now an indispensableresource for academic study, providing students with a wealth of material,including primary sources, lectures, book reviews, and much else besides. Theeasiest introduction is to use one of the many search engines available, and totype in your request, whether it be a specific philosopher (for example, Anselm)or a specific area of interest (for example, Existentialism). In all probabilitythere will then follow an almost limitless list of web-sites for you to surf. Thereare, however, some specific web-sites, which are worth mentioning here andwhich I have found particularly useful.1. There are three on-line encyclopedias of philosophy: the RoutledgeEncylopedia of Philosophy (www.rep.routledge.com), The Stanford Encyclopediaof Philosophy (www.plato.standford.edu) and the Internet Encyclopedia ofPhilosophy (www.utm.edu:80/research/iep/. Equally useful is The Dictionaryof Philosophical Terms and Names (www.people.delphi.com/gkemerling/dy/)and the research facility at erraticimpact.com. (See Appendix on page 348for instructions on searching the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy forinformation relating to The Question of God.)2. Some web-sites are excellent for providing links to other sites.EpistemeLincs.com includes thousands of sorted links to other philosophyresources, as does About.com Guide to Philosophy and Philosophy in Cyberspace.The Philosophy Department at Glasgow University (www.gla.ac.uk/Acad/Philosophy/links.html) is a model of its kind, and includes information aboutother philosophy departments, primary texts, and the job market.3. Most interesting of all are the dedicated web-sites, providing informationon individual philosophers. Again, the various search engines will help here. Ihave found the following to be particularly intriguing: the sites on Aquinas(www.aquinasonline.com), Hume (www.utm.edu/research/hume/hume.html)and Kant (www.hkbu.edu.hk/ ppp/Kant.html).

chapter 1COMMENTARYTHE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENTIntroduction: a priori and a posteriori arguments2Anselm’s argument: stage 14Anselm’s argument: stage 27Descartes’ ontological argument9The two stages of the argument: a summaryKant’s criticism of the ontological argument (first stage)11Kant’s criticism of the ontological argument (second stage)16The ontological argument revisited: Findlay and Malcolm19Karl Barth: a theological interpretation25Conclusion30QUESTIONSSOURCES11301 Anselm: The ontological argument312 Haight: An ontological argument for the Devil333 Descartes: The supremely perfect being354 Kant: The impossibility of an ontological proof365 Findlay: Disproof of God’s existence386 Malcolm: Anselm’s second ontological proof407 Hick: Necessary being42KEY TEXTS45BIBLIOGRAPHY45

2C O M M E N TA RYC O M M E N TA RYINTRODUCTION: A PRIORI AND A POSTERIORIARGUMENTSA priori propositionsThe ontological argument has had a long but chequered career. Mostfamously presented in the eleventh century by St Anselm, abbot of Bec andlater Archbishop of Canterbury, it was later rejected by St Thomas Aquinasin the twelfth century, then revived in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuriesby Descartes, Spinoza and Leibniz. In the eighteenth century, however,the criticisms made by Kant proved almost fatal, and as a result it was largelyignored for over a century and a half. In our own time, however, interest hasbeen rekindled by the work of philosophers and theologians such as Karl Barth(1931), Charles Hartshorne (1941), Norman Malcolm (1960), Alvin Plantinga(1974) and Carl Kordig (1981).1Certainly it is not difficult to see its fascination. Marked by an extremeformal elegance, it is unique among the arguments for God’s existence. This isso because it alone may be classified as an a priori argument, with all otherarguments for God’s existence being classified as a posteriori arguments. Whatdo these terms mean?The terms ‘a priori’ and ‘a posteriori’ distinguish between two typesof proposition: a proposition that is not dependent on experience and aproposition that is dependent on experience. So the statement ‘I cannot besimultaneously in the room and out of it’ is an a priori true proposition, whereasthe statement ‘This ball is square and round’ is an a priori false proposition.They are what philosophers call necessarily true and necessarily false, and noamount of experience or observation will render them otherwise. In one sense,of course, to say that a priori propositions make no appeal to experience ismisleading. After all, how can we say this of the two statements just cited whenthey include words like ‘room’ and ‘ball’? Surely without some experienceof, say, being in rooms and playing with balls, these terms would have nomeaning at all. The point is that, once we know what these terms mean,no experiential evidence is then required to determine the truth or falsity ofthe a priori statements in which they appear. Take the proposition ‘All bachelorsare unmarried men’. While it is certainly true that one requires some experience1. See Barth, Fides Quaerens Intellectum, Munich, Chr. Kaiser, 1931. English translation by IanRobertson, London, SCM Press, and Richmond, Va., John Knox Press, 1960; Hartshorne, Man’sVision of God (1941), reprinted Hamden, Conn., Archon Books, 1964; Anselm’s Discovery, LaSalle, Ill., Open Court, 1965, and The Logic of Perfection, La Salle, Ill., Open Court, 1962;Plantinga, The Nature of Necessity, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1974, and God, Freedom, and Evil,New York, Harper & Row, 1974; and Carl Kordig, ‘A Deontic Argument for God’s Existence’,Noûs, 15, 1981, pp. 207–228. According to Graham Oppy’s taxonomy there are no fewer thanseven major types of ontological argument. See Oppy, Ontological Arguments and Belief in God,New York, Cambridge University Press, 1995.

3T H E O N TO L O G I C A L A R G U M E N Tof the world to talk of bachelors in the first place, the truth of this propositiondoes not depend on this experience but on the definition of the term: being abachelor simply means being an unmarried man. In this sense it is a priori true:it provides its own verification and may be regarded as true in itself.The same, however, cannot be said of a posteriori propositions, like ‘Thesun is shining’ or ‘My cat is brown’. Whether these statements are true orfalse can only be decided by observation, by direct confrontation with theevidence. They are what we call contingently true or contingently false becausetheir truth or falsity is dependent (or contingent) on the circumstances, onwhat the world happens to be like. Unlike a priori propositions, therefore,a posteriori propositions are not universally and unconditionally true orfalse, nor do they provide their own corroboration, but are justified only tothe extent that they are verified or falsified by our experience. So we mustdistinguish between the statement ‘A bachelor is an unmarried man’ and thestatement ‘Mr Jones is a bachelor’. The first is a necessarily true proposition,proceeding from the definition of the term; and the second is a contingentproposition, which subsequent evidence may show to be either true or false.Which of the following statements are a priori true or false or aposteriori true or false?Triangles have three sides.The sun will rise tomorrow.Reagan was President of the UnitedStates.If A knows B, and if B knows C, thenA knows C.If A precedes B, and if B precedes C,then A precedes C.A posteriori propositionsEXERCISE 1.1No object can be completely redand green all over.A man cannot walk on water.Every man has a mother.I am reading this sentence.A straight line is the shortestdistance between two points.With this distinction between a priori and a posteriori behind us, we cannow appreciate why the ontological argument for God’s existence is unique.All the other arguments we shall look at – for example, the causal argument,the argument from design, the argument from miracles, and so on – base theircase on what is the most plausible explanation for various experiences wehave of the world. They do not argue that a particular explanation is bydefinition the only possible explanation but rather that, on the evidencebefore them, it is the only likely explanation. To this extent they have the formof a posteriori arguments. The ontological argument, on the other hand, isalone in maintaining that God’s existence can be established without recourseto empirical evidence – that is, evidence drawn from experience – and thussolely on the basis of an analysis of the concept of God. It is not, then, that ourWhy the ontologicalargument is unique

4C O M M E N TA RYexperience justifies the conclusion that God exists. It is rather that the very ideaof God implies that God exists, in much the same way as, say, the idea of atriangle implies a three-sided figure of 180 degrees. The proof of God lies, asit were, in the logic of ‘God’, in the logical implications of what we must sayabout him. To speak of God and to deny his existence is, as we shall now see,a contradiction in terms.St Anselm (c. 1033–1109)(left), Our lady of Bec(centre), Lanfranc (right)Born in Aosta, Italy, Anselm entered the monastery at Bec in Normandyas a novice in 1060, succeeding Lanfranc as prior in 1063, and becomingabbot in 1078. Under his direction Bec became a great intellectual centre,celebrated throughout Europe. It was during this period that Anselm wrotehis Monologium (1076) and Proslogium (1077–1078), the latter containinghis famous ontological argument. Anselm continued his ecclesiastical careerin England; it culminated in his appointment as the second NormanArchbishop of Canterbury in 1093. Generally recognized as the greatesttheologian of his day, he emphasized the priority of faith over reason,maintaining that truth was obtained only through fides quaerens intellectumor ‘faith seeking understanding’. Anselm’s tomb at Canterbury became anobject of veneration and pilgrimage and he was canonized in 1494.ANSELM’S ARGUMENT: STAGE 1Anselm’s definition of GodThe ontological argument was first presented by St Anselm in his Proslogium(chs 2–4) and in his Responsio to a contemporary critic, the monk Gaunilo(SOURCE 1: PP. 31–33).2 Many present-day commentators argue thatProslogium 2 and 4 present a different argument from Proslogium 3 and theResponsio. Whether this is so is a matter of some debate. What we can say,however, is that the second phase is structurally dependent on the first, andthat in the first phase Anselm is concerned to establish the fact of God’sexistence and in the second the nature of that existence.Anselm’s Proslogium 2 begins with a famous definition of God: ‘God issomething than which nothing greater can be conceived’ (‘aliquid quo nihilmaius cogitari possit’). The word ‘greater’ is admittedly ambiguous; but it soonbecomes clear that Anselm does not mean greater in size but greater in value– indeed, in the Proslogium, maius (‘greater’) is sometimes replaced bymelius (‘better’). Nor does Anselm make any attempt to fill in the details ofGod’s greatness or superiority. Nothing is said, for instance, of the attributestraditionally ascribed to him: his omnipotence, omniscience, immutability,2. Extracts are taken from Anselm: Basic Writings (Proslogium, Monologium, Gaunilo’s On Behalfof the Fool, Cur Deus Homo?) trans by S. N. Deane, with an Introduction by Charles Hartshorne,La Salle, Ill., Open Court, 1962.

5T H E O N TO L O G I C A L A R G U M E N Timpassibility, etc. Such descriptions of God’s qualities are rendered irrelevantby the very generality of Anselm’s definition. For whatever the qualitiesattributed to God (love, mercy), this definition means that God must possessthem to an absolute and ultimate degree (the most loving, the most merciful).Hence it is not just that God is the greatest conceivable being but rather that,being this being, he must possess all conceivable qualities to the greatestconceivable extent.Having set up this definition, Anselm proceeds to the second phase ofhis argument. Some people, of course, will deny that God exists. Such a oneis ‘the fool’ of Psalm 14:1, who ‘hath said in his heart: “There is no God.”’But what are we to make of this fool? The first thing to say is that, though hemay deny God’s actual existence in reality (in re), he does not, and cannot,deny God’s existence in his mind or understanding (in intellectu). This is sobecause to deny the existence of anything must presuppose the existence ofthat thing as an idea, i.e., as a thing existing in the mind. For example, if Ideny that unicorns exist, I must have an idea in my mind of what a unicornis like (i.e., a horse with a horn in its forehead). If I did not have this priorconcept of what a unicorn is, I could not then deny that such a thing exists.I would indeed have no idea of what I am denying. Now Anselm arguesthat the same holds for atheists. To deny God’s existence must presuppose aconcept of God in the mind. If they have no such concept, no such denial canbe made.Anselm next asks an apparently innocuous question. Which is greater,something that exists in the mind or something that also exists in reality? Firstconsider the following:Of the following choices, which would you prefer? Are they allappropriate examples of Anselm’s argument? What conclusionsdo you draw from your answers?1 To be shot by an imaginary bulletor by a real one?4 To fall in love with a real personor a fictional person?2 To be given an imaginary milliondollars or a real million dollars?5 To combat a real threat or animaginary threat?3 To fight an actual war or animaginary one?Anselm’s conclusion is that a thing is more valuable or more terrible, orindeed more anything, if it exists in reality than if it exists in the mind only.And from this he draws another conclusion: that the notion of the greatestconceivable being cannot be conceived in thought alone but must actually exist;that, in other words, any being that exists in reality will be greater than anybeing that is merely conceived of; and that consequently the greatestconceivable being, God, must exist.EXERCISE 1.2

6C O M M E N TA RYDistinction betweenintentional and formalexistenceIn order to clarify this, let us formulate Anselm’s argument in a slightlydifferent way. In differentiating between two kinds of existence – existence-inthe-mind and existence-in-reality – Anselm is presupposing an importantdistinction between what later philosophers have called intentional and formalexistence. Briefly put, intentional existence refers to the content of my idea (forexample, my idea of a baseball bat), and formal existence refers to the real thingin the world to which that idea refers (for example, the actual baseball bat inthe locker-room). Anselm’s own example is between the ideas a painter hasbefore painting (intentional) and the finished product, the actual painting(formal).Now, to repeat, Anselm has claimed that the concept of God is the conceptof the greatest conceivable being. He has also argued that even the atheist, indenying the existence of God, is denying the existence of this particular being.In other words, both the believer and the unbeliever, in affirming and denyingGod, have an idea of this being in their minds to begin with: they are boththinking of the intentional existence of God. But, Anselm asks, can the idea ofGod, as the greatest conceivable being, be merely the idea of an intentionalexistence? It cannot, he says. Why? Because if God’s existence is solely intentional, then it will be possible to conceive of a greater God, a God who isnot only an idea but who actually exists, who also has formal existence.For something is greater if it is both conceived of and exists than if it is merelyconceived of. Thus it follows that the being which exists only intentionallycannot be the greatest conceivable being: it lacks the extra attribute of real,formal existence. We may put this another way. Which is greater (i.e., whichcontains the greater number of attributes), the ‘idea of X’ or the ‘idea of anX that actually exists’? Clearly the latter because, unlike the former, it has theextra attribute of actual existence: it alone exists apart from the mind’sconception of it. Thus the thing that is the greatest conceivable being mustexist. For if it did not exist I could conceive of a greater thing by simply addingto it the extra quality of existence.Therefore, if that, than which nothing greater can be conceived, existsin the understanding alone, the very being, than which nothing greatercan be conceived, is one, than which a greater can be conceived. Butobviously this is impossible. Hence, there is no doubt that there exists abeing, than which nothing greater can be conceived, and it exists bothin the understanding and in reality.3Why atheists are ‘fools’We can now see why Anselm considers atheists fools. If they accept the ideaof God but deny his actual existence, they are involved in a blatantcontradiction, a contradiction as obvious as the denial that triangles are threesided figures. They are denying what is implied in the idea of the greatestconceivable being – namely, that this being must exist, must possess theadditional attribute of formal existence. What they are saying, in effect, is that3. Ibid., p. 11.

7T H E O N TO L O G I C A L A R G U M E N Tthey r

Anselm’s argument: stage 2 7 Descartes’ ontological argument 9 The two stages of the argument: a summary 11 Kant’s criticism of the ontological argument (first stage) 11 Kant’s criticism of the ontological argument (second stage) 16 The ontological argument revisited: Findlay and Malcolm 19 Karl Barth: a theological interpretation 25

Related Documents:

May 02, 2018 · D. Program Evaluation ͟The organization has provided a description of the framework for how each program will be evaluated. The framework should include all the elements below: ͟The evaluation methods are cost-effective for the organization ͟Quantitative and qualitative data is being collected (at Basics tier, data collection must have begun)

Silat is a combative art of self-defense and survival rooted from Matay archipelago. It was traced at thé early of Langkasuka Kingdom (2nd century CE) till thé reign of Melaka (Malaysia) Sultanate era (13th century). Silat has now evolved to become part of social culture and tradition with thé appearance of a fine physical and spiritual .

On an exceptional basis, Member States may request UNESCO to provide thé candidates with access to thé platform so they can complète thé form by themselves. Thèse requests must be addressed to esd rize unesco. or by 15 A ril 2021 UNESCO will provide thé nomineewith accessto thé platform via their émail address.

̶The leading indicator of employee engagement is based on the quality of the relationship between employee and supervisor Empower your managers! ̶Help them understand the impact on the organization ̶Share important changes, plan options, tasks, and deadlines ̶Provide key messages and talking points ̶Prepare them to answer employee questions

Dr. Sunita Bharatwal** Dr. Pawan Garga*** Abstract Customer satisfaction is derived from thè functionalities and values, a product or Service can provide. The current study aims to segregate thè dimensions of ordine Service quality and gather insights on its impact on web shopping. The trends of purchases have

Chính Văn.- Còn đức Thế tôn thì tuệ giác cực kỳ trong sạch 8: hiện hành bất nhị 9, đạt đến vô tướng 10, đứng vào chỗ đứng của các đức Thế tôn 11, thể hiện tính bình đẳng của các Ngài, đến chỗ không còn chướng ngại 12, giáo pháp không thể khuynh đảo, tâm thức không bị cản trở, cái được

1.6.1 A religious knowledge curriculum 26 1.6.2 A religious studies curriculum 27 1.6.3 A religious education curriculum 27 1.7 Religious knowledge and the national curriculum 29 1.8 Religious knowledge and the humanities 31 1.9 Conclusion 35 CHAPTER TWO: REVIEW OF THE RELIGIOUS KNOWLEDGE CURRICULUM IN NIGERIA 36 2.1 The development of the religious knowledge curriculum in 36 2.1.1 The .

Le genou de Lucy. Odile Jacob. 1999. Coppens Y. Pré-textes. L’homme préhistorique en morceaux. Eds Odile Jacob. 2011. Costentin J., Delaveau P. Café, thé, chocolat, les bons effets sur le cerveau et pour le corps. Editions Odile Jacob. 2010. Crawford M., Marsh D. The driving force : food in human evolution and the future.